imtoken钱包下载操作教程|femininity
imtoken钱包下载操作教程|femininity
Femininity - Wikipedia
Femininity - Wikipedia
Jump to content
Main menu
Main menu
move to sidebar
hide
Navigation
Main pageContentsCurrent eventsRandom articleAbout WikipediaContact usDonate
Contribute
HelpLearn to editCommunity portalRecent changesUpload file
Search
Search
Create account
Log in
Personal tools
Create account Log in
Pages for logged out editors learn more
ContributionsTalk
Contents
move to sidebar
hide
(Top)
1Overview and history
2Behavior and personality
3Clothing and appearance
Toggle Clothing and appearance subsection
3.1In history
3.2Body alteration
4Traditional roles
Toggle Traditional roles subsection
4.1Explanations for occupational imbalance
4.1.1Role congruity theory
5Religion and politics
Toggle Religion and politics subsection
5.1Asian religions
5.2Abrahamic theology
5.3Communism
6In men
7Feminist views
Toggle Feminist views subsection
7.1Julia Serano's transfeminist critique
8See also
9References
10External links
Toggle the table of contents
Femininity
51 languages
العربيةAzərbaycancaবাংলাBân-lâm-gúBikol CentralCatalàČeštinaCymraegDanskDeutschΕλληνικάEspañolEsperantoEuskaraفارسیFrançaisFryskGalego한국어ՀայերենBahasa IndonesiaItalianoעבריתJawaLietuviųLingálaМакедонскиBahasa MelayuNederlandsनेपाल भाषा日本語Oʻzbekcha / ўзбекчаPolskiPortuguêsRomânăРусскийسرائیکیSimple EnglishکوردیСрпски / srpskiSuomiSvenskaTagalogதமிழ்ไทยTürkçeУкраїнськаاردوTiếng Việt粵語中文
Edit links
ArticleTalk
English
ReadEditView history
Tools
Tools
move to sidebar
hide
Actions
ReadEditView history
General
What links hereRelated changesUpload fileSpecial pagesPermanent linkPage informationCite this pageGet shortened URLDownload QR codeWikidata item
Print/export
Download as PDFPrintable version
In other projects
Wikimedia CommonsWikiquote
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
This is the latest accepted revision, reviewed on 4 March 2024.
"Feminine" redirects here. For other uses, see Feminine (disambiguation).
Attributes associated with women
Venus with a Mirror (c. 1555) by Titian, showing the goddess Venus as the personification of femininity
Femininity (also called womanliness) is a set of attributes, behaviors, and roles generally associated with women and girls. Femininity can be understood as socially constructed,[1][2] and there is also some evidence that some behaviors considered feminine are influenced by both cultural factors and biological factors.[1][3][4][5] To what extent femininity is biologically or socially influenced is subject to debate.[3][4][5] It is conceptually distinct from both the female biological sex and from womanhood, as all humans can exhibit feminine and masculine traits, regardless of sex and gender.[2]
Traits traditionally cited as feminine include gracefulness, gentleness, empathy, humility, and sensitivity, though traits associated with femininity vary across societies and individuals, and are influenced by a variety of social and cultural factors.[citation needed]
Overview and history[edit]
The Birth of Venus (1486, Uffizi) is a classic representation of femininity painted by Sandro Botticelli.[6][7] Venus was a Roman goddess principally associated with love, beauty and fertility.
Despite the terms femininity and masculinity being in common usage, there is little scientific agreement about what femininity and masculinity are.[3]: 5 Among scholars, the concept of femininity has varying meanings.[8]
Professor of English Tara Williams has suggested that modern notions of femininity in English-speaking society began during the medieval period at the time of the bubonic plague in the 1300s.[9] Women in the Early Middle Ages were referred to simply within their traditional roles of maiden, wife, or widow.[9]: 4 After the Black Death in England wiped out approximately half the population, traditional gender roles of wife and mother changed, and opportunities opened up for women in society. The words femininity and womanhood are first recorded in Chaucer around 1380.[10][11]
In 1949, French intellectual Simone de Beauvoir wrote that "no biological, psychological or economic fate determines the figure that the human female presents in society" and "one is not born, but rather becomes, a woman".[12] The idea was picked up in 1959 by Canadian-American sociologist Erving Goffman[13] and in 1990 by American philosopher Judith Butler,[14] who theorized that gender is not fixed or inherent but is rather a socially defined set of practices and traits that have, over time, grown to become labelled as feminine or masculine.[15] Goffman argued that women are socialized to present themselves as "precious, ornamental and fragile, uninstructed in and ill-suited for anything requiring muscular exertion" and to project "shyness, reserve and a display of frailty, fear and incompetence".[16]
Scientific efforts to measure femininity and masculinity were pioneered by psychologists Lewis Terman and Catherine Cox Miles in the 1930s. Their M–F model was adopted by other researchers and psychologists. The model posited that femininity and masculinity were innate and enduring qualities, not easily measured, opposite to one another, and that imbalances between them led to mental disorders.[17]
Alongside the women's movement of the 1970s, researchers began to move away from the M–F model, developing an interest in androgyny.[17] The Bem Sex Role Inventory and the Personal Attributes Questionnaire were developed to measure femininity and masculinity on separate scales. Using such tests, researchers found that the two dimensions varied independently of one another, casting doubt on the earlier view of femininity and masculinity as opposing qualities.[17]
Second-wave feminists, influenced by de Beauvoir, believed that although biological differences between females and males were innate, the concepts of femininity and masculinity had been culturally constructed, with traits such as passivity and tenderness assigned to women and aggression and intelligence assigned to men.[18][19] Girls, second-wave feminists said, were then socialized with toys, games, television, and school into conforming to feminine values and behaviors.[18] In her significant 1963 book The Feminine Mystique, American feminist Betty Friedan wrote that the key to women's subjugation lay in the social construction of femininity as childlike, passive, and dependent,[20] and called for a "drastic reshaping of the cultural image of femininity."[21]
Behavior and personality[edit]
See also: Sex differences in psychology, Feminine psychology, and Nature versus nurture
Traits such as nurturance, sensitivity, sweetness,[8] supportiveness,[22][23] gentleness,
[23][24] warmth,[22][24] passivity, cooperativeness, expressiveness,[17] modesty, humility, empathy,[23] affection, tenderness,[22] and being emotional, kind, helpful, devoted, and understanding[24] have been cited as stereotypically feminine. The defining characteristics of femininity vary between and even within societies.[22]
Portrait of Charlotte du Val d'Ognes by Marie-Denise Villers, 1801, Metropolitan Museum of Art (possibly a self-portrait), depicts an independent feminine spirit.[25]
The relationship between feminine socialization and heterosexual relationships has been studied by scholars, as femininity is related to women's and girls' sexual appeal to men and boys.[8] Femininity is sometimes linked with sexual objectification.[26][27] Sexual passiveness, or sexual receptivity, is sometimes considered feminine while sexual assertiveness and sexual desire are sometimes considered masculine.[27]
Scholars have debated the extent to which gender identity and gender-specific behaviors are due to socialization versus biological factors.[5]: 29 [28][29] Social and biological influences are thought to be mutually interacting during development.[5]: 29 [4]: 218–225 Studies of prenatal androgen exposure have provided some evidence that femininity and masculinity are partly biologically determined.[3]: 8–9 [4]: 153–154 Other possible biological influences include evolution, genetics, epigenetics, and hormones (both during development and in adulthood).[5]: 29–31 [3]: 7–13 [4]: 153–154
In 1959, researchers such as John Money and Anke Ehrhardt proposed the prenatal hormone theory. Their research argues that sexual organs bathe the embryo with hormones in the womb, resulting in the birth of an individual with a distinctively male or female brain; this was suggested by some to "predict future behavioral development in a masculine or feminine direction".[30] This theory, however, has been criticized on theoretical and empirical grounds and remains controversial.[31][32] In 2005, scientific research investigating sex differences in psychology showed that gender expectations and stereotype threat affect behavior, and a person's gender identity can develop as early as three years of age.[33] Money also argued that gender identity is formed during a child's first three years.[29]
People who exhibit a combination of both masculine and feminine characteristics are considered androgynous, and feminist philosophers have argued that gender ambiguity may blur gender classification.[34][35] Modern conceptualizations of femininity also rely not just upon social constructions, but upon the individualized choices made by women.[36]
Philosopher Mary Vetterling-Braggin argues that all characteristics associated with femininity arose from early human sexual encounters which were mainly male-forced and female-unwilling, because of male and female anatomical differences.[37][page needed] Others, such as Carole Pateman, Ria Kloppenborg, and Wouter J. Hanegraaff, argue that the definition of femininity is the result of how females must behave in order to maintain a patriarchal social system.[26][38]
In his 1998 book Masculinity and Femininity: the Taboo Dimension of National Cultures, Dutch psychologist and researcher Geert Hofstede wrote that only behaviors directly connected with procreation can, strictly speaking, be described as feminine or masculine, and yet every society worldwide recognizes many additional behaviors as more suitable to females than males, and vice versa. He describes these as relatively arbitrary choices mediated by cultural norms and traditions, identifying "masculinity versus femininity" as one of five basic dimensions in his theory of cultural dimensions. Hofstede describes as feminine behaviors including service, permissiveness, and benevolence, and describes as feminine those countries stressing equality, solidarity, quality of work-life, and the resolution of conflicts by compromise and negotiation.[39][40]
In Carl Jung's school of analytical psychology, the anima and animus are the two primary anthropomorphic archetypes of the unconscious mind. The anima and animus are described by Jung as elements of his theory of the collective unconscious, a domain of the unconscious that transcends the personal psyche. In the unconscious of the male, it finds expression as a feminine inner personality: anima; equivalently, in the unconscious of the female, it is expressed as a masculine inner personality: animus.[41]
Clothing and appearance[edit]
Main articles: Physical attractiveness § Female, and Clothing § Gender differentiation
See also: Gendered associations of pink and blue
In Western cultures, the ideal of feminine appearance has traditionally included long, flowing hair, clear skin, a narrow waist, and little or no body hair or facial hair.[2][42][43] In other cultures, however, some expectations are different. For example, in many parts of the world, underarm hair is not considered unfeminine.[44] Today, the color pink is strongly associated with femininity, whereas in the early 1900s pink was associated with boys and blue with girls.[45]
These feminine ideals of beauty have been criticized as restrictive, unhealthy, and even racist.[43][46] In particular, the prevalence of anorexia and other eating disorders in Western countries has frequently been blamed on the modern feminine ideal of thinness.[47]
Muslim woman wearing a headdress (Hijab)
In many Muslim countries, women are required to cover their heads with a hijab (veil). It is considered a symbol of feminine modesty and morality.[48][49] Some, however, see it as a symbol of objectification and oppression.[50][51]
In history[edit]
In some cultures, cosmetics are associated with femininity.
Cultural standards vary on what is considered feminine. For example, in 16th century France, high heels were considered a distinctly masculine type of shoe, though they are currently considered feminine.[52][53]
In Ancient Egypt, sheath and beaded net dresses were considered female clothing, while wraparound dresses, perfumes, cosmetics, and elaborate jewelry were worn by both men and women. In Ancient Persia, clothing was generally unisex, though women wore veils and headscarves. Women in Ancient Greece wore himations; and in Ancient Rome women wore the palla, a rectangular mantle, and the maphorion.[54]
The typical feminine outfit of aristocratic women of the Renaissance was an undershirt with a gown and a high-waisted overgown, and a plucked forehead and beehive or turban-style hairdo.[54]
Body alteration[edit]
Main article: Body alteration
Body alteration is the deliberate altering of the human body for aesthetic or non-medical purpose.[55] One such purpose has been to induce perceived feminine characteristics in women.
For centuries in Imperial China, smaller feet were considered to be a more aristocratic characteristic in women. The practice of foot binding was intended to enhance this characteristic, though it made walking difficult and painful.[56][57]
In a few parts of Africa and Asia, neck rings are worn in order to elongate the neck. In these cultures, a long neck characterizes feminine beauty.[58] The Padaung of Burma and Tutsi women of Burundi, for instance, practice this form of body modification.[59][60]
In China until the twentieth century, tiny, bound feet for women were considered aristocratic and feminine.
The Kayan people of Burma (Myanmar) associate the wearing of neck rings with feminine beauty.[61]
Traditional roles[edit]
Main article: Gender roles
Teacher in a classroom in Madagascar (c. 2008). Primary and secondary school teaching is often considered a feminine occupation.
Femininity as a social construct relies on a binary gender system that treats men and masculinity as different from, and opposite to, women and femininity.[8] In patriarchal societies, including Western ones, conventional attitudes to femininity contribute to the subordination of women, as women are seen as more compliant, vulnerable, and less prone to violence.[8]
Gender stereotypes influence traditional feminine occupations, resulting in microaggression toward women who break traditional gender roles.[62] These stereotypes include that women have a caring nature, have skill at household-related work, have greater manual dexterity than men, are more honest than men, and have a more attractive physical appearance. Occupational roles associated with these stereotypes include: midwife, teacher, accountant, data entry clerk, cashier, salesperson, receptionist, housekeeper, cook, maid, social worker, and nurse.[63] Occupational segregation maintains gender inequality[64] and the gender pay gap.[65] Certain medical specializations, such as surgery and emergency medicine, are dominated by a masculine culture[66] and have a higher salary.[67][68]
Leadership is associated with masculinity in Western culture and women are perceived less favorably as potential leaders.[69] However, some people have argued that feminine-style leadership, which is associated with leadership that focuses on help and cooperation, is advantageous over masculine leadership, which is associated with focusing on tasks and control.[70] Female leaders are more often described by Western media using characteristics associated with femininity, such as emotion.[70]
Explanations for occupational imbalance[edit]
Psychologist Deborah L. Best argues that primary sex characteristics of men and women, such as the ability to bear children, caused a historical sexual division of labor and that gender stereotypes evolved culturally to perpetuate this division.[71]
The practice of bearing children tends to interrupt the continuity of employment. According to human capital theory, this retracts from the female investment in higher education and employment training. Richard Anker of the International Labour Office argues human capital theory does not explain the sexual division of labor because many occupations tied to feminine roles, such as administrative assistance, require more knowledge, experience, and continuity of employment than low-skilled masculinized occupations, such as truck driving. Anker argues the feminization of certain occupations limits employment options for women.[63]
Role congruity theory[edit]
Role congruity theory proposes that people tend to view deviations from expected gender roles negatively. It supports the empirical evidence that gender discrimination exists in areas traditionally associated with one gender or the other. It is sometimes used to explain why people have a tendency to evaluate behavior that fulfills the prescriptions of a leader role less favorably when it is enacted by a woman.[72][73][74][75][76]
Religion and politics[edit]
The Altai consider shamanism a feminine role.[77]
Asian religions[edit]
Shamanism may have originated as early as the Paleolithic period, predating all organized religions.[78][79] Archeological finds have suggested that the earliest known shamans were female,[80] and contemporary shamanic roles such as the Korean mudang continue to be filled primarily by women.[81][82]
In Hindu traditions, Devi is the female aspect of the divine. Shakti is the divine feminine creative power, the sacred force that moves through the entire universe[83] and the agent of change. She is the female counterpart without whom the male aspect, which represents consciousness or discrimination, remains impotent and void. As the female manifestation of the supreme lord, she is also called Prakriti, the basic nature of intelligence by which the Universe exists and functions. In Hinduism, the universal creative force Yoni is feminine, with inspiration being the life force of creation.
Yin and yang
In Taoism, the concept of yin represents the primary force of the female half of yin and yang. The yin is also present, to a smaller proportion, in the male half. The yin can be characterized as slow, soft, yielding, diffuse, cold, wet, and passive.[84]
Abrahamic theology[edit]
Holy Wisdom: Hagia Sophia
Although the Abrahamic God is typically described in masculine terms—such as father or king—many theologians argue that this is not meant to indicate the gender of God.[85] According to the Catechism of the Catholic Church, God "is neither man nor woman: he is God".[86] Several recent writers, such as feminist theologian Sallie McFague, have explored the idea of "God as mother", examining the feminine qualities attributed to God. For example, in the Book of Isaiah, God is compared to a mother comforting her child, while in the Book of Deuteronomy, God is said to have given birth to Israel.[85]
The Book of Genesis describes the divine creation of the world out of nothing or ex nihilo. In Wisdom literature and in the wisdom tradition, wisdom is described as feminine. In many books of the Old Testament, including Wisdom and Sirach, wisdom is personified and called she. According to David Winston, because wisdom is God's "creative agent," she must be intimately identified with God.[87]
The Wisdom of God is feminine in Hebrew: Chokhmah, in Arabic: Hikmah, in Greek: Sophia, and in Latin: Sapientia. In Hebrew, both Shekhinah (the Holy Spirit and divine presence of God) and Ruach HaKodesh (divine inspiration) are feminine.[citation needed]
In Christian Kabbalah, Chokhmah (wisdom and intuition) is the force in the creative process that God used to create the heavens and the earth. Binah (understanding and perception) is the great mother, the feminine receiver of energy and giver of form. Binah receives the intuitive insight from Chokhmah and dwells on it in the same way that a mother receives the seed from the father, and keeps it within her until it's time to give birth. The intuition, once received and contemplated with perception, leads to the creation of the Universe.[88]
Communism[edit]
Porcelain statue of a woman in communist China - Cat Street Market, Hong Kong
Communist revolutionaries initially depicted idealized womanhood as muscular, plainly dressed and strong,[89] with good female communists shown as undertaking hard manual labour, using guns, and eschewing self-adornment.[90] Contemporary Western journalists portrayed communist states as the enemy of traditional femininity, describing women in communist countries as "mannish" perversions.[91][92] In revolutionary China in the 1950s, Western journalists described Chinese women as "drably dressed, usually in sloppy slacks and without makeup, hair waves or nail polish" and wrote that "Glamour was communism's earliest victim in China. You can stroll the cheerless streets of Peking all day, without seeing a skirt or a sign of lipstick; without thrilling to the faintest breath of perfume; without hearing the click of high heels, or catching the glint of legs sheathed in nylon."[93][94] In communist Poland, changing from high heels to worker's boots symbolized women's shift from the bourgeois to socialism."[95]
Later, the initial state portrayals of idealized femininity as strong and hard-working began to also include more traditional notions such as gentleness, caring and nurturing behaviour, softness, modesty and moral virtue,[89][96]: 53 requiring good communist women to become "superheroes who excelled in all spheres", including working at jobs not traditionally regarded as feminine in nature.[96]: 55–60
Communist ideology explicitly rejected some aspects of traditional femininity that it viewed as bourgeois and consumerist, such as helplessness, idleness and self-adornment. In Communist countries, some women resented not having access to cosmetics and fashionable clothes. In her 1993 book of essays How We Survived Communism & Even Laughed, Croatian journalist and novelist Slavenka Drakulic wrote about "a complaint I heard repeatedly from women in Warsaw, Budapest, Prague, Sofia, East Berlin: 'Look at us – we don't even look like women. There are no deodorants, perfumes, sometimes even no soap or toothpaste. There is no fine underwear, no pantyhose, no nice lingerie[']"[97] : 31 and "Sometimes I think the real Iron Curtain is made of silky, shiny images of pretty women dressed in wonderful clothes, of pictures from women's magazines ... The images that cross the borders in magazines, movies or videos are therefore more dangerous than any secret weapon, because they make one desire that 'otherness' badly enough to risk one's life trying to escape."[97] : 28–9
As communist countries such as Romania and the Soviet Union began to liberalize, their official media began representing women in more conventionally feminine ways compared with the "rotund farm workers and plain-Jane factory hand" depictions they had previously been publishing. As perfumes, cosmetics, fashionable clothing, and footwear became available to ordinary women in the Soviet Union, East Germany, Poland, Yugoslavia and Hungary, they began to be presented not as bourgeois frivolities but as signs of socialist modernity.[98] In China, with the economic liberation started by Deng Xiaoping in the 1980s, the state stopped discouraging women from expressing conventional femininity, and gender stereotypes and commercialized sexualization of women which had been suppressed under communist ideology began to rise.[99]
In men[edit]
See also: Effeminacy
Flowers and makeup are stereotypically associated with femininity in Western culture.[100][101]
In many cultures, men who display qualities considered feminine are often stigmatized and labeled as weak.[8] Effeminate men are often associated with homosexuality,[102][103] although femininity is not necessarily related to a man's sexual orientation.[104] Because men are pressured to be masculine and heterosexual, feminine men are assumed to be gay or queer because of how they perform their gender. This assumption limits the way one is allowed to express one's gender and sexuality.[105][106]
Cross-dressing and drag are two public performances of femininity by men that have been popularly known and understood throughout many western cultures. Men who wear clothing associated with femininity are often called cross-dressers.[107] A drag queen is a man who wears flamboyant women's clothing and behaves in an exaggeratedly feminine manner for entertainment purposes.
Feminist views[edit]
Part of a series onFeminism
History
Feminist history
History of feminism
Women's history
American
British
Canadian
German
Waves
First
Second
Third
Fourth
Timelines
Women's suffrage
Muslim countries
US
Other women's rights
Women's suffrage by country
Austria
Australia
Canada
Colombia
India
Japan
Kuwait
Liechtenstein
New Zealand
Spain
Second Republic
Francoist
Switzerland
United Kingdom
Cayman Islands
Wales
United States
states
Intersectional variants
Fat
Lesbian
Lesbian of color
Radical lesbianism
Separatist
Sex-positive
Transfeminism
Postgenderism
Vegetarian ecofeminism
Socialist
Anarchist
Queer
Jineology
Marxist
Critical theory
Standpoint
Materialist
Ecofeminist
Postcolonial
Global
Transnational
Xenofeminism
Multicultural
Africana womanism
Black
Hip hop
Lesbian
Ratchet
Chicana
Lesbian
Indigenous
Native American
Multiracial
Romani
Womanism
Conservative variants
Anti-abortion
Equity
Femonationalism
Maternal
Postfeminism
Neofeminism
Reactionary
State
Carceral
Imperial
Embedded
Gender-critical
Victim
White
Religious variants
Atheist
Buddhist
Christian
Mormon
New
Womanist
Asian
Neopagan
Dianic Wicca
Reclaiming
Ecofeminist
Hindu
Islamic
Jewish
Orthodox
Sikh
Movements and ideologies
Analytical
Anti-fascist
Anti-pornography
Cyberfeminism
HCI
Networked
Ecofeminism
Eugenic
Individualist
Lipstick
Stiletto
Liberal
Difference
Equality
Social
Labor
Libertarian
Post-structural
Postmodern
Radical
Cultural
Political lesbianism
Separatist
Technofeminism
Women's liberation
Concepts
Literature
Children's literature
Discrimination against transgender women
Diversity (politics)
Diversity, equity, and inclusion
Effects on society
Equality
Female education
Female genital mutilation
Femicide
Feminationalism
Feminism in culture
Feminist movement
African-American women's suffrage movement
Art movement
In hip hop
Feminist stripper
Gender equality
Girl power
Honor killing
Ideal womanhood
Internalized sexism
International Girl's Day and Women's Day
Language reform
Likeability trap
Male privilege
Matriarchal religion
Media
Men in feminism
Misogyny
Oedipus complex
Opposition to feminism
Pro-feminism
Protofeminism
Purple capitalism
Purplewashing
Reproductive justice
Sex workers' rights
Sexual harassment
Sexual objectification
Toxic masculinity
Transmisogyny
Triple oppression
Violence against women
War on women
Women's empowerment
Women-only space
Women's health
Women's rights
Women in the workforce
Outlooks
Bicycling and feminism
Criticism of marriage
Views on BDSM
Views on pornography
Views on prostitution
Views on sexual orientation
Views on sexuality
Views on transgender topics
Theory
Feminist method
Gender studies
Gender mainstreaming
Gynocentrism
Kyriarchy
Male gaze
Matriarchy
Women's studies
Men's studies
Patriarchy
Écriture féminine
Areas of study
Anthropology
Archaeology
Architecture
Art
Art criticism
Literary criticism
Film theory
Science fiction
Biology
Composition studies
Criminology
Pathways perspective
Economics
FDPA
Geography
International relations
Constructivism
Legal theory
Pedagogy
Philosophy
Aesthetics
Empiricism
Epistemology
Ethics
Justice ethics
Existentialism
Metaphysics
science
Political ecology
Political theory
Pornography
Psychology
Therapy
Revisionist mythology
Sex wars
Sexology
Sociology
Technoscience
Theology
womanist theology
By country
Albania
Australia
Bangladesh
Canada
China
Democratic Republic of the Congo
Denmark
Egypt
Ethiopia
Finland
France
Germany
Ghana
Greece
Hong Kong
India
Indonesia
Iran
Iraq
Republic of Ireland
Israel
Italy
Japan
Latin America
Argentina
Brazil
Chile
Haiti
Honduras
Mexico
Paraguay
Trinidad and Tobago
Lebanon
Malaysia
Mali
Nepal
Netherlands
New Zealand
Nigeria
Northern Cyprus
Norway
Pakistan
Philippines
Poland
Russia
Syria
Saudi Arabia
South Africa
South Korea
Sweden
Taiwan
Thailand
Turkey
Vietnam
Ukraine
United Kingdom
United States
History of women
Lists and categories
Lists
Articles
Feminists
by nationality
Literature
American feminist literature
Feminist comic books
Feminist songs
Conservative feminisms
Ecofeminist authors
Feminist art critics
Feminist economists
Feminist philosophers
Feminist poets
Feminist rhetoricians
Jewish feminists
Muslim feminists
Feminist parties
Suffragists and suffragettes
Women's rights activists
Women's studies journals
Women's suffrage organizations
Categories
Women's rights by country
Feminists by nationality
Feminism portalvte
See also: Feminism
Feminist philosophers such as Judith Butler and Simone de Beauvoir[108] contend that femininity and masculinity are created through repeated performances of gender; these performances reproduce and define the traditional categories of sex and/or gender.[109]
Many second-wave feminists reject what they regard as constricting standards of female beauty, created for the subordination and objectifying of women and self-perpetuated by reproductive competition and women's own aesthetics.[110]
Others, such as lipstick feminists and some other third-wave feminists, argue that feminism should not devalue feminine culture and identity, and that symbols of feminine identity such as make-up, suggestive clothing and having a sexual allure can be valid and empowering personal choices for both sexes.[111][112]
Julia Serano notes that masculine girls and women face much less social disapproval than feminine boys and men, which she attributes to sexism. Serano argues that women wanting to be like men is consistent with the idea that maleness is more valued in contemporary culture than femaleness, whereas men being willing to give up masculinity in favour of femininity directly threatens the notion of male superiority as well as the idea that men and women should be opposites. To support her thesis, Serano cites the far greater public scrutiny and disdain experienced by male-to-female cross-dressers compared with that faced by women who dress in masculine clothes, as well as research showing that parents are likelier to respond negatively to sons who like Barbie dolls and ballet or wear nail polish than they are to daughters exhibiting comparably masculine behaviours.[113]: 284–292
Julia Serano's transfeminist critique[edit]
This section may lend undue weight to certain ideas, incidents, or controversies. Please help improve it by rewriting it in a balanced fashion that contextualizes different points of view. (July 2022) (Learn how and when to remove this template message)
In her 2007 book Whipping Girl: A Transsexual Woman on Sexism and the Scapegoating of Femininity, American transsexual writer and biologist Julia Serano offers a transfeminist critique of femininity, notable especially for its call to empower femininity:[113][114]
Serano notes that some behaviors, such as frequent smiling or avoiding eye contact with strangers, are considered feminine because they are practised disproportionately by women, and likely have resulted from women's attempts to negotiate through a world which is sometimes hostile to them.[113]: 322
Serano argues that because contemporary culture is sexist, it assigns negative connotations to, or trivializes, behaviours understood to be feminine such as gossiping, behaving emotionally or decorating. It also recasts and reimagines femininity through a male heterosexual lens, for example interpreting women's empathy and altruism as husband-and-child-focused rather than globally focused, and interpreting women's interest in aesthetics as intended solely to entice or attract men.[113]: 327–8
See also[edit]
Feminine psychology
Feminism
Feminization (sociology)
Effeminacy
Gender role
Gender studies
Marianismo
Masculinity
Nature versus nurture
Sociology of gender
Transfeminine
References[edit]
^ a b Shehan, Constance L. (2018). Gale Researcher Guide for: The Continuing Significance of Gender. Gale, Cengage Learning. pp. 1–5. ISBN 9781535861175.
^ a b c Ferrante, Joan (January 2010). Sociology: A Global Perspective (7th ed.). Belmont, CA: Thomson Wadsworth. pp. 269–272. ISBN 978-0-8400-3204-1.
^ a b c d e Martin, Hale; Finn, Stephen E. (2010). Masculinity and Femininity in the MMPI-2 and MMPI-A. University of Minnesota Press. pp. 5–13. ISBN 978-0-8166-2444-7.
^ a b c d e Lippa, Richard A. (2005). Gender, Nature, and Nurture (2nd ed.). Routledge. pp. 153–154, 218–225. ISBN 9781135604257.
^ a b c d e Wharton, Amy S. (2005). The Sociology of Gender: An Introduction to Theory and Research. John Wiley & Sons. pp. 29–31. ISBN 978-1-40-514343-1.
^ Manifestations of Venus: art and sexuality pg 93 By Katie Scott, Caroline Arscott pg 93-"...began its consideration of Venus by describing her as .... who presided over all feminine charms, for..."
^ The Pacific muse pg 49 By Patty O'Brien "The young beautiful Venus wringing water from her tresses was a configuration of exotic femininity that was…
^ a b c d e f Windsor, Elroi J. (2015). "Femininities". In Wright, James D. (ed.). International Encyclopedia of the Social & Behavioral Sciences, Volume 8 (2nd ed.). Elsevier. pp. 893–897. doi:10.1016/B978-0-08-097086-8.35015-2. ISBN 978-0-08-097087-5.
^ a b Williams, Tara (2011). Inventing Womanhood: Gender and Language in Later Middle English Writing (PDF). Ohio State University Press. ISBN 978-0814211519. Archived from the original (PDF) on November 6, 2016. Retrieved August 14, 2013.
^ "c1386 CHAUCER Man of Law's T. 262 O serpent under femynynytee.". Oxford English Dictionary (Online ed.). Oxford University Press. (Subscription or participating institution membership required.)
^ "c1374 CHAUCER Troylus I. 283 Alle here lymes so wel answerynge Weren to womanhode.". Oxford English Dictionary (Online ed.). Oxford University Press. (Subscription or participating institution membership required.)
^ de Beauvoir, Simone (2010). The Second Sex. New York: Knopf. ISBN 978-0307265562.
^ Erving Goffman (1959). The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life. Anchor. ISBN 0385094027.
^ Butler, Judith (1990). Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. Routledge. ISBN 0415389550.
^ Milestone, Katie (2011). Gender and Popular Culture. Polity. ISBN 978-0745643946.
^ Ziegler, Kathryn A. (2010). "Formidable-Femininity": Performing Gender and Third Wave Feminism in a Women's Self-Defense Class. LAP LAMBERT Academic Publishing. p. 10. ISBN 978-3838307671.
^ a b c d Stets, Jan E.; Burke, Peter J. (2000). "Femininity/Masculinity". In Borgatta, Edgar F.; Montgomery, Rhonda (eds.). Encyclopedia of Sociology, Volume 2 (2nd ed.). Macmillan Reference USA. pp. 997–1005. ISBN 0-02-864850-1.
^ a b Millett, Kate (1968). Sexual Politics.
^ Hollows, Joanne (2000). Feminism, Femininity and Popular Culture. Manchester University Press. pp. 10–12. ISBN 0719043956.
^ Jaggar, Alison M. (1989). Gender/Body/Knowledge: Feminist Reconstructions of Being and Knowing. Rutgers University Press. pp. 17. ISBN 0813513790.
^ Gamble, Sarah (2002). The Routledge Companion to Feminism and Postfeminism. Routledge. pp. 29. ISBN 0415243106.
^ a b c d Burke, Peter J.; Stets, Jan E. (2009). Identity Theory. Oxford University Press. p. 63. ISBN 978-0-19-538827-5.
^ a b c Vetterling-Braggin, Mary, ed. (1982). 'Femininity,' 'Masculinity,' and 'Androgyny': A Modern Philosophical Discussion. Rowman & Allanheld. p. 5. ISBN 0-8226-0399-3.
^ a b c Kite, Mary E. (2001). "Gender Stereotypes". In Worell, Judith (ed.). Encyclopedia of Women and Gender, Volume 1. Academic Press. p. 563. ISBN 0-12-227245-5.
^ [1] The Methodologies of Art: An Introduction (Boulder: Westview Press, 1996), 81. Laurie Schneider Adams "[Young Woman Drawing] 'suddenly acquired feminine attributes: Its poetry, literary … all seem to reveal the feminine spirit."
^ a b Ria Kloppenborg, Wouter J. Hanegraaff, Female stereotypes in religious traditions, BRILL, 1995, ISBN 90-04-10290-6, ISBN 978-90-04-10290-3
^ a b Ussher, Jane M. Fantasies of femininity: reframing the boundaries of sex
^ van den Wijngaard, Marianne (1997). Reinventing the Sexes: The Biomedical Construction of Femininity and Masculinity. Indiana University Press. p. 1. ISBN 0-253-21087-9.
^ a b Pearson, Judy C.; Cooks, Leda (1995). "Gender and Power". In Kalbfleisch, Pamela J.; Cody, Michael J. (eds.). Gender, power, and communication in human relationships. Psychology Press. p. 333. ISBN 0-8058-1404-3. Retrieved June 3, 2011.[permanent dead link]
^ van den Wijngaard (1997), p. 5.
^ Ehrhardt, Anke A.; H. F. L. Meyer-Bahlburg (1981). "Effects of Prenatal Sex Hormones on Gender-Related Behavior". Science. 211 (4488): 1312–1318. Bibcode:1981Sci...211.1312E. doi:10.1126/science.7209510. PMID 7209510.
^ Bem, Sandra Lipsitz (1993). The Lenses of Gender: Transforming the Debate on Sexual Inequality. New Haven u.a.: Yale University Press. pp. 25–27. ISBN 0-300-05676-1.
^ Ann M. Gallagher, James C. Kaufman, Gender differences in mathematics: an integrative psychological approach, Cambridge University Press, 2005, ISBN 0-521-82605-5, ISBN 978-0-521-82605-1
^ Butler, Judith (1999 [1990]), Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity (New York and London: Routledge).
^ Laurie, Timothy (2014). "The ethics of nobody I know: Gender and the politics of description". Qualitative Research Journal. 14: 64–78. doi:10.1108/QRJ-03-2014-0011. hdl:10453/44221.
^ Budgeon, Shelley(2015), 'Individualized femininity and feminist politics of choice..', European Journal of Women's Studies, 22 (3), pp. 303-318.
^ Vetterling-Braggin (1982).
^ Pateman, Carole (1988). The Sexual Contract, Stanford: Stanford University Press, p. 207.
^ Hofstede, Geert (1998). Masculinity and Femininity: The Taboo Dimension of National Cultures. SAGE Publications, Inc. ISBN 0761910298.
^ "National Culture: Dimensions". The Hofstede Centre. Archived from the original on August 31, 2013. Retrieved August 14, 2013. The masculinity side of this dimension represents a preference in society for achievement, heroism, assertiveness and material reward for success. Society at large is more competitive. Its opposite, femininity, stands for a preference for cooperation, modesty, caring for the weak and quality of life. Society at large is more consensus-oriented.
^ Jung, Carl. The Psychology of the Unconscious, Dvir Co., Ltd., Tel-Aviv, 1973 (originally 1917)
^ Lesnik-Oberstein, Karín (2010). The Last Taboo: Women and Body Hair (Paperback ed.). Manchester University Press. ISBN 978-0-7190-8323-5.
^ a b Davis, Kathy (2003). Dubious Equalities and Embodied Differences: Cultural Studies on Cosmetic Surgery. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield. p. 93. ISBN 0-7425-1421-8.
^ McLoughlin, Linda (2000). The Language of Magazines. London: Routledge. p. 96. ISBN 0-415-21424-6.
^ Bolich, G. G. (2007). Conversing on Gender. Gardners Books. p. 315. ISBN 978-0615156705.
^ Taylor, Verta (2008). Feminist Frontiers (8th ed.). New York: McGraw Hill Higher Education. p. 157. ISBN 978-0-07-340430-1.
^ Mahowald, Mary Briody (1996). Women and Children in Health Care: An Unequal Majority (New ed.). New York: Oxford University Press. pp. 210–213. ISBN 978-0-19-510870-5.
^ Daniels, Dayna B. (2009). Polygendered and Ponytailed: The Dilemma of Femininity and the Female Athlete. Toronto: Women's Press. p. 147. ISBN 978-0889614765.
^ Esposito, John L., ed. (2003). The Oxford Dictionary of Islam. New York: Oxford University Press. p. 112. ISBN 0195125584.
^ "Wearing the Hijab in Solidarity Perpetuates Oppression". www.nytimes.com.
^ "I didn't want to wear my hijab, and don't believe very young girls should wear them today | Iman Amrani". the Guardian. February 2, 2018.
^ Brown, William, Art of shoe making, Global Media, 2007, 8189940295, 9788189940294
^ Kremer, William (January 24, 2013). "Why did men stop wearing high heels?". BBC News. Retrieved January 25, 2013.
^ a b Condra, Jill, The Greenwood encyclopedia of clothing through world history: Prehistory to 1500 CE, Greenwood Publishing Group, 2008, ISBN 0-313-33663-6, ISBN 978-0-313-33663-8
^ "What is body modification?". Essortment.com. May 16, 1986. Archived from the original on January 28, 2016. Retrieved November 13, 2011.
^ "Binding: Bone Breaking Beauty, August, 2009". Cogitz.com. August 29, 2009. Archived from the original on July 9, 2012. Retrieved November 13, 2011.
^ "The Art of Social Change: Campaigns against foot-binding and genital mutilation". The New York Times. October 22, 2010.
^ Kislenko, Arne. Culture and customs of Thailand. Westport, Conn.: Greenwood Press, 2004, ISBN 978-0-313-32128-3.
^ Thesander, Marianne. The feminine ideal. London: Reaktion Books, 1997, ISBN 978-1-86189-004-7.
^ Walker, Andrew. "Bound by tradition". Archived from the original on May 22, 2015. Retrieved July 25, 2011.
^ Keng, Huay Pu. "Long Neck Ring Wearing". www.huaypukeng.com. Retrieved October 22, 2017.
^ Derald, Sue (2010). Microaggressions in everyday life: race, gender, and sexual orientation. US, Canada: John Wiley and Sons. p. 172. ISBN 978-0-470-49140-9.
^ a b Anker, Richard (2001). Gender and Jobs: Sex Segregation of Occupations in the World (2. impr. with modifications. ed.). Geneva: International Labour Office. pp. 23–30. ISBN 978-92-2-109524-8.
^ "Women's Rights Law Reporter". Litigation-essentials.lexisnexis.com. Retrieved November 13, 2011.
^ Beckford, Martin (August 11, 2009). "More British women in 'high status' professions than men, finds study". The Daily Telegraph. UK. Archived from the original on January 12, 2022. Retrieved November 13, 2011.
^ Boulis, Ann K.; Jacobs, Jerry A. (2010). The Changing Face of Medicine: Women Doctors and the Evolution of Health Care in America. Ithaca, N.Y.: ILR. pp. 94–98. ISBN 978-0-8014-7662-4.
^ "Annual Survey of Hours and Earnings, 2012 Provisional Results". UK: Office for National Statistics.
^ Rogers, Simon (November 22, 2012). "What each job gets paid: find yours and see how it compares". The Guardian. Retrieved August 16, 2013.
^ Chin, Jean Lau, Women and leadership: transforming visions and diverse voices Wiley-Blackwell, 2007, ISBN 1-4051-5582-5, ISBN 978-1-4051-5582-3
^ a b Klenke, Karin, Women and Leadership: A Contextual Perspective , Springer Publishing Company, 2004 ISBN 0-8261-9221-1, ISBN 978-0-8261-9221-9
^ Best, Deborah L. (2001). "Cross-Cultural Gender Roles". In Worell, Judith (ed.). Encyclopedia of Women and Gender, Volume 1. Academic Press. p. 281. ISBN 0-12-227245-5.
^ Eagly, Alice H.; Karau, Steven J. (2002). "Role congruity theory of prejudice toward female leaders". Psychological Review. 109 (3): 573–598. doi:10.1037/0033-295X.109.3.573. PMID 12088246. S2CID 1283792.
^ Heilman, Madeline E.; Wallen, Aaron S.; Fuchs, Daniella; Tamkins, Melinda M. (2004). "Penalties for Success: Reactions to Women Who Succeed at Male Gender-Typed Tasks" (PDF). Journal of Applied Psychology. 89 (3): 416–427. doi:10.1037/0021-9010.89.3.416. PMID 15161402. Archived from the original (PDF) on October 30, 2011. Retrieved July 23, 2011.
^ Rudman, Laurie A.; Glick, Peter (2001). "Prescriptive Gender Stereotypes and Backlash Towards Agentic Women". Journal of Social Issues. 57 (4): 743–762. doi:10.1111/0022-4537.00239. hdl:2027.42/146421. ISBN 9781405100847. S2CID 54219902.
^ Heilman, Madeline E (2001). "Description and Prescription: How Gender Stereotypes Prevent Women's Ascent Up the Organizational Ladder". Journal of Social Issues. 57 (4): 657–674. doi:10.1111/0022-4537.00234. ISBN 9781405100847. S2CID 144504496.
^ Schein, Virginia E (2001). "A Global Look at Psychological Barriers to Women's Progress in Management". Journal of Social Issues. 57 (4): 675–688. doi:10.1111/0022-4537.00235. ISBN 9781405100847.
^ Barbara Tedlock The woman in the shaman's body: reclaiming the feminine in religion and medicine, Random House Digital, Inc., 2005
^ Jean Clottes. "Shamanism in Prehistory". Bradshaw foundation. Archived from the original on September 28, 2011. Retrieved March 11, 2008.
^ Karl J. Narr. "Prehistoric religion". Britannica Online Encyclopedia 2008. Archived from the original on April 14, 2015. Retrieved March 28, 2008.
^ Tedlock, Barbara. 2005. The Woman in the Shaman's Body: Reclaiming the Feminine in Religion and Medicine. New York: Bantam.
^ Lee, Jung Yong (August 1973). "Concerning the Origin and Formation of Korean Shamanism". Numen. 20 (2): 135–159. doi:10.1163/156852773x00321. PMID 11615020.
^ Oak, Sung-Deuk (2010). "Healing and Exorcism: Christian Encounters with Shamanism in Early Modern Korea". Asian Ethnology. 69 (1): 95–128.
^ Sacred Sanskrit words, p.111
^ Osgood, Charles E (1973). "From Yang and Yin to and or but". Language. 49 (2): 380–412. doi:10.2307/412460. JSTOR 412460.
^ a b McGrath, Alister E. (2010). Christian Theology: An Introduction (5th ed.). Wiley-Blackwell. pp. 197–199. ISBN 978-1-4443-3514-9.
^ "Catechism of the Catholic Church". Archived from the original on March 3, 2013. Retrieved February 12, 2016.
^ David Winston, The Wisdom of Solomon: a new translation with introduction and commentary, (New York, Doubleday, 1979), p. 194 ISBN 0-385-01644-1
^ "The Kabbalah Of Isaac Luria Glossary". Christ-centeredkabbalah.org. Archived from the original on January 28, 2012. Retrieved November 13, 2011.
^ a b Brown, Archie (2009). The Rise and Fall of Communism (1st U.S. ed.). New York: Ecco. p. 70. ISBN 978-0061138799.
^ Gilmartin, Christina K.; Hershatter, Gail; Rofel, Lisa, eds. (1994). Engendering China: Women, Culture, and the State. Cambridge (Mass.): Harvard University Press. p. 304. ISBN 0674253329.
^ Lanzona, Vina A. (2009). Amazons of the Huk Rebellion: Gender, Sex, and Revolution in the Philippines (New Perspectives in Southeast Asian Studies). University of Wisconsin Press. p. 182. ISBN 978-0299230944.
^ Strahan, Lachlan (1996). Australia's China: Changing Perceptions from the 1930s to the 1990s. Cambridge [England]: Cambridge University Press. p. 242. ISBN 0521484979.
^ Strahan, Lachlan (1996). Australia's China: Changing Perceptions from the 1930s to the 1990s. Cambridge [England]: Cambridge University Press. pp. 234–240. ISBN 0521484979.
^ Turner, Bryan S.; Yangwen, Zheng, eds. (2009). The Body in Asia. New York: Berghahn Books. p. 183. ISBN 978-1845455507.
^ Fidelis, Malgorzata (2010). Women, Communism, and Industrialization in Postwar Poland (1. publ. ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. p. 113. ISBN 978-0521196871.
^ a b Fawn, Rick; White, Stephen, eds. (2002). Russia after Communism (1 ed.). London: Cass. ISBN 0714652938.
^ a b Drakulić, Slavenka (2003). How we Survived Communism and even Laughed (1. HarperPerennial ed., repr. ed.). New York: HarperPerennial. ISBN 0060975407.
^ Bren, Paulina; Neuburger, Mary, eds. (September 20, 2012). Communism Unwrapped: Consumption in Cold War Eastern Europe. New York, NY: Oxford University Press. p. 230. ISBN 978-0199827671.
^ Halpern, Diane F. and Fanny M. Cheung (2010). Women at the Top: Powerful Leaders Tell Us How to Combine Work and Family. Wiley-Blackwell. ISBN 978-1405171052.
^ Elias, Ann (2015). Useless Beauty: Flowers and Australian Art. Cambridge Scholars Publishing. p. 45. ISBN 978-1-4438-8457-0. On a global scale, flowers have not only defined femininity but the history of representations of flowers in art has underpinned differences in the sexual categories of masculine and feminine.
^ Beausoleil, Natalie (1994). "Makeup in Everyday Life". In Sault, Nicole (ed.). Many Mirrors: Body Image and Social Relations. Rutgers University Press. p. 33. ISBN 978-0-8135-2080-3. Among everyday appearance practices in contemporary Western society, 'visible' makeup clearly marks the production of 'womanhood' and 'femininity': overall, women are the ones who wear makeup, men do not.
^ "Why do gays fall for straights?" The Advocate, February 17, 1998, 72 pages, No. 753, ISSN 0001-8996, Published by Here Publishing
^ Pezzote, Angelo Straight Acting: Gay Men, Masculinity and Finding True Love, Kensington Publishing Corp., 2008, ISBN 0-7582-1943-1, ISBN 978-0-7582-1943-5
^ Hill, Darryl B (2006). "Feminine" Heterosexual Men: Subverting Heteropatriarchal Sexual Scripts?". Journal of Men's Studies. 14 (2): 145–59. doi:10.3149/jms.1402.145 (inactive January 31, 2024). S2CID 145293218.{{cite journal}}: CS1 maint: DOI inactive as of January 2024 (link)
^ Taywaditep, Kittiwut Jod (2001). "Marginalization Among the Marginalized: Gay Men's Anti-Effeminacy Attitudes". Journal of Homosexuality. 42 (1): 1–28. doi:10.1300/j082v42n01_01. PMID 11991561. S2CID 9163739.
^ Fellows, Will, A Passion to Preserve: Gay Men as Keepers of Culture, University of Wisconsin Press, 2005, ISBN 0-299-19684-4, ISBN 978-0-299-19684-4
^ cross-dress." The American Heritage Dictionary of the English Language, Fourth Edition. Houghton Mifflin Company, 2004.
^ van den Wijngaard (1997), p. 4.
^ Butler, J. (1990). Gender trouble: Feminism and the subversion of identity. New York; Routledge.
^ "Sally Feldman – Heights of madness". New Humanist. May 7, 2008. Retrieved November 13, 2011.
^ Scanlon, Jennifer, Bad girls go everywhere: the life of Helen Gurley Brown, Oxford University Press US, 2009, ISBN 0-19-534205-4, ISBN 978-0-19-534205-5
^ Joanne Hollows; Rachel Moseley (February 17, 2006). Feminism in popular culture. Berg Publishers. p. 84. ISBN 978-1-84520-223-1. https://books.google.com/books?
^ a b c d Serano, Julia (2007). Whipping Girl: A Transsexual Woman on Sexism and the Scapegoating of Femininity. Berkeley: Seal Press. ISBN 978-1580051545. Until feminists work to empower femininity and pry it away from the insipid, inferior meanings that plague it – weakness, helplessness, fragility, passivity, frivolity, and artificiality – those meanings will continue to haunt every person who is female and/or feminine.
^ Rasmussen, Debbie (2007). "Risk: Feminine Protection (interview with Julia Serano)". Bitch. Archived from the original on September 15, 2013. Retrieved 15 August 2013. The rising visibility of trans, intersex, and genderqueer movements has led feminists—and, to a lesser extent, the rest of the world—to an increasing awareness that m and f are only the beginning of the story of gender identity. With the release of Whipping Girl: A Transsexual Woman on Sexism and the Scapegoating of Femininity, Julia Serano offers a perspective sorely needed, but up until now rarely heard: a transfeminine critique of both feminist and mainstream understandings of gender.
External links[edit]
Quotations related to Femininity at Wikiquote
The dictionary definition of femininity at Wiktionary
Media related to Femininity at Wikimedia Commons
Links to related articles
vteFeminismHistoryGeneral
Timeline
First-wave
Second-wave
timeline
Third-wave
Fourth-wave
Social
Bicycling and feminism
Feminist history
Women's history
Timeline of women's legal rights (other than voting)
Women's suffrage
Timeline
Australia
Canada
Japan
Kuwait
Majority-Muslim countries
New Zealand
Switzerland
United Kingdom
Wales
United States
Timeline
African-American
States of
Utah
Virginia
Wyoming
MovementsandideologiesGeneral
Analytical
Anarchist
Anti-abortion
Anti-fascist
Atheist
Carceral
Choice
Conservative
Cultural
Cyber
HCI
Difference
Eco
Vegetarian
Equality
Eugenic
Fat
Gender-critical
Global
Hip hop
Activism
Individualist
Labor
Lesbian
Liberal
Equity
Lipstick
Materialist
Maternal
Neo
New
Post
Postcolonial
Postmodern
Post-structural
French
Radical
Separatism
Sex-positive
Social
Socialist
Marxist
Standpoint
State
Trans
Transnational
Victim
Womanism
Africana
Women's liberation
Religious
Atheist
Buddhist
Christian
Mormon
New
Womanist
Asian
Neopagan
Dianic Wicca
Reclaiming
Ecofeminist
Hindu
Islamic
Jewish
Orthodox
SikhEthnic and racial
Black
Chicana
Indigenous
Kurdish (Jineology)
Native American
Sámi
Jewish
Mizrahi
Romani
White
Concepts
Literature
Children's literature
Discrimination against transgender women
Diversity (politics)
Diversity, equity, and inclusion
Effects on society
Equality
Female education
Female genital mutilation
Femicide
Feminationalism
Feminism in culture
Feminist movement
African-American women's suffrage movement
Art movement
In hip hop
Feminist stripper
Gender equality
Girl power
Honor killing
Ideal womanhood
Internalized sexism
International Girl's Day and Women's Day
Language reform
Likeability trap
Male privilege
Matriarchal religion
Media
Men in feminism
Misogyny
Oedipus complex
Opposition to feminism
Pro-feminism
Protofeminism
Purple capitalism
Purplewashing
Reproductive justice
Sex workers' rights
Sexual harassment
Sexual objectification
Toxic masculinity
Transmisogyny
Triple oppression
Violence against women
War on women
Women's empowerment
Women-only space
Women's health
Women's rights
Women in the workforceTheory
Gender studies
Gender mainstreaming
Gynocentrism
Matriarchy
Women's studies
Men's studies
Kyriarchy
Patriarchy
Écriture féminine
Economics
Post-structuralist discourse analysis
Method
Oedipus complex
Political theory
Theology
Thealogy
Womanist
Sexology
Sociology
Rhetoric
Legal theory
Art
Art criticism
Literary criticism
Film theory
Biology
Political ecology
Architecture
Anthropology
Archaeology
Criminology
Pathways perspective
Geography
Pedagogy
Philosophy
Aesthetics
Empiricism
Epistemology
Ethics
Justice ethics
Existentialism
Metaphysics
Science
Pornography
Psychology
Therapy
Seriality
International relations
Existentialism
Revisionist mythology
Technoscience
Science fiction
Composition studies
By country
Albania
Australia
Bangladesh
Canada
China
Democratic Republic of the Congo
Denmark
Egypt
Ethiopia
Finland
France
Germany
Ghana
Greece
Hong Kong
India
Indonesia
Iran
Iraq
Republic of Ireland
Israel
Italy
Japan
Latin America
Argentina
Brazil
Chile
Haiti
Honduras
Mexico
Paraguay
Trinidad and Tobago
Lebanon
Malaysia
Mali
Nepal
Netherlands
New Zealand
Nigeria
Northern Cyprus
Norway
Pakistan
Philippines
Poland
Russia
Syria
Saudi Arabia
South Africa
South Korea
Sweden
Taiwan
Thailand
Turkey
Vietnam
Ukraine
United Kingdom
United States
History of womenListsPeople
Art critics
Ecofeminist authors
Economists
Jewish
Muslim
Philosophers
Poets
Rhetoricians
Suffragists and suffragettes
Women's rights activists
Other
Conservative feminisms
Literature
American
Comic books
Parties
Women's studies journals
Feminism portal
Category
Index
Authority control databases International
FAST
National
France
BnF data
Germany
Israel
United States
Czech Republic
Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Femininity&oldid=1211857021"
Category: FemininityHidden categories: All articles with dead external linksArticles with dead external links from August 2023Articles with permanently dead external linksCS1 maint: DOI inactive as of January 2024Articles with short descriptionShort description is different from WikidataWikipedia pending changes protected pagesUse mdy dates from November 2011All articles with unsourced statementsArticles with unsourced statements from September 2023Wikipedia articles needing page number citations from October 2019Articles with unsourced statements from February 2022Pages using sidebar with the child parameterWikipedia neutral point of view disputes from July 2022All Wikipedia neutral point of view disputesCommons category link from WikidataArticles with excerptsArticles with FAST identifiersArticles with BNF identifiersArticles with BNFdata identifiersArticles with GND identifiersArticles with J9U identifiersArticles with LCCN identifiersArticles with NKC identifiers
This page was last edited on 4 March 2024, at 21:18 (UTC).
Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License 4.0;
additional terms may apply. By using this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.
Privacy policy
About Wikipedia
Disclaimers
Contact Wikipedia
Code of Conduct
Developers
Statistics
Cookie statement
Mobile view
Toggle limited content width
Page restricted | ScienceDirect
Page restricted | ScienceDirect
Your Browser is out of date.
Update your browser to view ScienceDirect.
View recommended browsers.
Request details:
Request ID: 8636431c2c8684ac-HKG
IP: 49.157.13.121
UTC time: 2024-03-12T19:41:31+00:00
Browser: Mozilla/5.0 (Windows NT 10.0; Win64; x64) AppleWebKit/537.36 (KHTML, like Gecko) Chrome/97.0.4692.71 Safari/537.36
About ScienceDirect
Shopping cart
Contact and support
Terms and conditions
Privacy policy
Cookies are used by this site. By continuing you agree to the use of cookies.
Copyright © 2024 Elsevier B.V., its licensors, and contributors. All rights are reserved, including those for text and data mining, AI training, and similar technologies. For all open access content, the Creative Commons licensing terms apply.
FEMININITY | English meaning - Cambridge Dictionary
FEMININITY | English meaning - Cambridge Dictionary
Dictionary
Translate
Grammar
Thesaurus
+Plus
Cambridge Dictionary +Plus
Shop
Cambridge Dictionary +Plus
My profile
+Plus help
Log out
Cambridge Dictionary +Plus
My profile
+Plus help
Log out
Log in
/
Sign up
English (UK)
Search
Search
English
Meaning of femininity in English
femininitynoun [ U ]
usually approving uk
Your browser doesn't support HTML5 audio
/ˌfem.əˈnɪn.ə.ti/ us
Your browser doesn't support HTML5 audio
/ˌfem.əˈnɪn.ə.t̬i/
Add to word list
Add to word list
the fact or quality of having characteristics that are traditionally thought to be typical of or suitable for a woman: Long hair was traditionally regarded as a sign of femininity. The flowers and cream lace of the dress indicate femininity and delicacy. See
feminine
More examplesFewer examplesParents should be careful about the notions of masculinity and femininity they convey to their children.She feels that working women should not be reluctant to express their femininity.Her soft voice and gentle femininity made her a favourite leading lady in his films.
(Definition of femininity from the Cambridge Advanced Learner's Dictionary & Thesaurus © Cambridge University Press)
Examples of femininity
femininity
They experienced their clothes and appearance as expressive, and closely linked to a sense of their own femininity.
From the Cambridge English Corpus
Thus, men repress their own feelings, devalue femininity because of its emotional side, are afraid of women and disappointing in their relationships with them.
From the Cambridge English Corpus
As her legs became emancipated, markers of her femininity migrated upwards, making her another ambiguous creature.
From the Cambridge English Corpus
Parisian consumption was the opposite, oriented not towards male activity, but towards a consumerism controlled by a femininity that distracted men from productive work.
From the Cambridge English Corpus
The second part concentrated more specifically on exploring their understandings of masculinity and femininity in relation to soldiering.
From the Cambridge English Corpus
Since the late 1970s, critics intrigued by the idea that music can enact gender, have heard their music as somehow embodying femininity.
From the Cambridge English Corpus
The association of masculinity with the cerebral and femininity with the physical perhaps explains women's exclusion from credibility on these grounds.
From the Cambridge English Corpus
These have in common declining social status and degradation of selfimage, as the cultural ideal, youthful femininity, can no longer be met.
From the Cambridge English Corpus
This global interpretation, which is not based in contextualized empirical analysis, assumes a direct mapping among discourse, femininity, and powerlessness.
From the Cambridge English Corpus
Certainly, she rejected - or possibly never even considered - using her femininity to personal and political advantage.
From the Cambridge English Corpus
It is the intersection of assertions of femininity with cultural, class and racial identity which would have enriched this chapter beyond the discussion of dress.
From the Cambridge English Corpus
And, conversely, histories of motherhood - and femininity - seemed so much more important in the development of new gender ideologies and practices.
From the Cambridge English Corpus
Each song draws the listener into an image of femininity while threatening assumptions hinted at in the lyrics.
From the Cambridge English Corpus
Offering formal training for teaching, which implied that women needed to be taught to teach, endangered this understanding of femininity.
From the Cambridge English Corpus
More generally, it reflects the dualistic opposition of masculinity versus femininity and mind versus body that is so prevalent in our culture.
From the Cambridge English Corpus
See all examples of femininity
These examples are from corpora and from sources on the web. Any opinions in the examples do not represent the opinion of the Cambridge Dictionary editors or of Cambridge University Press or its licensors.
What is the pronunciation of femininity?
B1
Translations of femininity
in Chinese (Traditional)
女性氣質, 女性特點…
See more
in Chinese (Simplified)
女性气质, 女性特点…
See more
in Spanish
feminidad, feminidad [feminine]…
See more
in Portuguese
feminilidade, feminilidade [feminine]…
See more
in more languages
in Japanese
in Turkish
in French
in Catalan
in Dutch
in Danish
in Swedish
in Malay
in German
in Norwegian
in Ukrainian
in Russian
in Arabic
in Czech
in Indonesian
in Thai
in Vietnamese
in Polish
in Korean
in Italian
女らしさ, 女(おんな)らしさ…
See more
dişilik, kadınlık, kadınlık özelliği…
See more
féminité [feminine], féminité…
See more
feminitat…
See more
vrouwelijkheid…
See more
femininitet, kvindelighed…
See more
kvinnlighet…
See more
kewanitaan…
See more
die Weiblichkeit…
See more
kvinnelighet [masculine], feminitet [masculine], kvinnelighet…
See more
жіночність…
See more
женственность…
See more
اُنوثة…
See more
ženskost…
See more
kewanitaan…
See more
ความเป็นผู้หญิง…
See more
nữ tính…
See more
kobiecość…
See more
여성스러움…
See more
femminilità…
See more
Need a translator?
Get a quick, free translation!
Translator tool
Browse
Femidom
feminine
feminine hygiene
femininely
femininity
feminism
feminist
feminity
feminization
More meanings of femininity
All
femininity noun, at feminine
See all meanings
Word of the Day
response
UK
Your browser doesn't support HTML5 audio
/rɪˈspɒns/
US
Your browser doesn't support HTML5 audio
/rɪˈspɑːns/
an answer or reaction
About this
Blog
Forget doing it or forget to do it? Avoiding common mistakes with verb patterns (2)
March 06, 2024
Read More
New Words
inverse vaccine
March 11, 2024
More new words
has been added to list
To top
Contents
EnglishExamplesTranslations
© Cambridge University Press & Assessment 2024
Learn
Learn
Learn
New Words
Help
In Print
Word of the Year 2021
Word of the Year 2022
Word of the Year 2023
Develop
Develop
Develop
Dictionary API
Double-Click Lookup
Search Widgets
License Data
About
About
About
Accessibility
Cambridge English
Cambridge University Press & Assessment
Consent Management
Cookies and Privacy
Corpus
Terms of Use
© Cambridge University Press & Assessment 2024
Cambridge Dictionary +Plus
My profile
+Plus help
Log out
Dictionary
Definitions
Clear explanations of natural written and spoken English
English
Learner’s Dictionary
Essential British English
Essential American English
Translations
Click on the arrows to change the translation direction.
Bilingual Dictionaries
English–Chinese (Simplified)
Chinese (Simplified)–English
English–Chinese (Traditional)
Chinese (Traditional)–English
English–Dutch
Dutch–English
English–French
French–English
English–German
German–English
English–Indonesian
Indonesian–English
English–Italian
Italian–English
English–Japanese
Japanese–English
English–Norwegian
Norwegian–English
English–Polish
Polish–English
English–Portuguese
Portuguese–English
English–Spanish
Spanish–English
English–Swedish
Swedish–English
Semi-bilingual Dictionaries
English–Arabic
English–Bengali
English–Catalan
English–Czech
English–Danish
English–Gujarati
English–Hindi
English–Korean
English–Malay
English–Marathi
English–Russian
English–Tamil
English–Telugu
English–Thai
English–Turkish
English–Ukrainian
English–Urdu
English–Vietnamese
Translate
Grammar
Thesaurus
Pronunciation
Cambridge Dictionary +Plus
Shop
Cambridge Dictionary +Plus
My profile
+Plus help
Log out
Log in /
Sign up
English (UK)
Change
English (UK)
English (US)
Español
Русский
Português
Deutsch
Français
Italiano
中文 (简体)
正體中文 (繁體)
Polski
한국어
Türkçe
日本語
Tiếng Việt
Nederlands
Svenska
Dansk
Norsk
हिंदी
বাঙ্গালি
मराठी
ગુજરાતી
தமிழ்
తెలుగు
Українська
Follow us
Choose a dictionary
Recent and Recommended
Definitions
Clear explanations of natural written and spoken English
English
Learner’s Dictionary
Essential British English
Essential American English
Grammar and thesaurus
Usage explanations of natural written and spoken English
Grammar
Thesaurus
Pronunciation
British and American pronunciations with audio
English Pronunciation
Translation
Click on the arrows to change the translation direction.
Bilingual Dictionaries
English–Chinese (Simplified)
Chinese (Simplified)–English
English–Chinese (Traditional)
Chinese (Traditional)–English
English–Dutch
Dutch–English
English–French
French–English
English–German
German–English
English–Indonesian
Indonesian–English
English–Italian
Italian–English
English–Japanese
Japanese–English
English–Norwegian
Norwegian–English
English–Polish
Polish–English
English–Portuguese
Portuguese–English
English–Spanish
Spanish–English
English–Swedish
Swedish–English
Semi-bilingual Dictionaries
English–Arabic
English–Bengali
English–Catalan
English–Czech
English–Danish
English–Gujarati
English–Hindi
English–Korean
English–Malay
English–Marathi
English–Russian
English–Tamil
English–Telugu
English–Thai
English–Turkish
English–Ukrainian
English–Urdu
English–Vietnamese
Dictionary +Plus
Word Lists
Choose your language
English (UK)
English (US)
Español
Русский
Português
Deutsch
Français
Italiano
中文 (简体)
正體中文 (繁體)
Polski
한국어
Türkçe
日本語
Tiếng Việt
Nederlands
Svenska
Dansk
Norsk
हिंदी
বাঙ্গালি
मराठी
ગુજરાતી
தமிழ்
తెలుగు
Українська
Contents
English
Noun
Examples
Translations
Grammar
All translations
My word lists
Add femininity to one of your lists below, or create a new one.
More
Go to your word lists
Tell us about this example sentence:
The word in the example sentence does not match the entry word.
The sentence contains offensive content.
Cancel
Submit
The word in the example sentence does not match the entry word.
The sentence contains offensive content.
Cancel
Submit
Masculinity vs Femininity: Similarities and Differences (2024)
Masculinity vs Femininity: Similarities and Differences (2024)
Skip to content
Main Menu
Home
Essay Plan Templates
Choose a SubjectMenu Toggle
Sociology
Psychology
Education Studies
TeamMenu Toggle
About The Helpful Professor
Peer Review and Editorial Process
Meet the Team
Contact
Our YouTube Channel
Search for:
Search
Masculinity vs Femininity: Similarities and DifferencesBy
Chris Drew (PhD)
/ October 18, 2023 /
Leave a Comment
The distinction between masculinity and femininity primarily concerns societal expectations, behaviors, and social roles typically associated with males and females.
The differences relate to social and cultural understandings about the social behaviors and roles of these two genders, whereas the categories of ‘male’ and ‘female’ relate to biological understandings of biological sexes.
For a brief introduction, these are the two binary gender identities:
Femininity typically embodies traits related to nurturing, emotional expression, and collaboration (Basow, 1992). Women, for example, are often expected to show more emotion, communicate effectively and non-aggressively, and prioritize nurturing relationships over assertive behavior. Think about a typical film character who is nurturing her children (e.g., Mrs. Doubtfire’s character), or a woman leading a team through conflict resolution rather than dominance.
Masculinity tends to align with traits such as assertiveness, independence, and dominance (Connell & Messerschmidt, 2015). Men are often encouraged to suppress emotion, strive for independence and display assertiveness or even aggressiveness. A real-world example might be a Hollywood action hero, physically strong and emotionally guarded (e.g., James Bond).
As these descriptors are cultural descriptions of expected behaviors, they are not strictly connected to the genders. For example, many women can, and do, exhibit masculine traits to a greater or lesser extent. As such, these traits are seen as socially constructed, and extensive research underscores the spectrum of masculine and feminine behaviors rather than rigidly dichotomous categories.
Contents
show
Masculinity vs Femininity
Masculinity
Masculinity Examples
Femininity
Femininity Examples
Table of Differences Between Femininity and Masculinity
Cultural Variations in Masculine and Feminine Stereotypes
Conclusion
References
Masculinity vs Femininity
Masculinity
Masculinity refers to the qualities, characteristics or roles conventionally associated with men (Kimmel & Aronson, 2011).
Traditionally, many societies value traits such as strength, aggression, and independence in men. These are often internalized by children through media and parental expectations in a process called gender socialization.
Masculinity is not limited to men, as women can, and often do, exhibit masculine traits.
Gender theorists have also explored the concept of “hegemonic masculinity” (Connell & Messerschmidt, 2015), which refers to a particular configuration of practice that legitimizes men’s dominant position in society and justifies the subordination of women, and other marginalized ways of being male.
An instance demonstrating this can be seen in most superhero movies like “Superman” where the male lead character is depicted as physically dominant, emotionally detached and rescues those in trouble.
See also: Toxic Masculinity Definition and Examples
However, it is vital not to oversimplify or stereotype these traits.
Modern perspectives of masculinity emphasize plurality, intersectionality and fluid dynamics (Bridges & Pascoe, 2014). Plurality suggests that there are many ways to express masculinity, not just a rigid stereotype.
For example, consider the trend of stay-at-home dads, which reflects a valid expression of masculinity contrary to the societal norm. Intersectionality discusses how different factors such as race, class, age or sexual orientation interact with masculinity, which results in varied experiences of it.
The fluid nature of masculinity underscores that it can change within an individual over time due to numerous factors including personal growth or cultural shifts.
Masculinity Examples
The following are traits traditionally associated with hegemonic masculinity. Please note that these are generalized, traditional, and often outdated stereotypes, and do not necessarily apply to every individual.
Physical Strength: Men are often judged by their physical capabilities, such as their strength, endurance, and athletic prowess (Bridges & Pascoe, 2014). An example would be professional athletes like Usain Bolt who are renowned for their physical abilities.
Emotional Control: Men are typically encouraged to suppress their emotions as a sign of strength (Kimmel & Aronson, 2011). Consider the phrase “real men don’t cry,” which discourages emotional vulnerability.
Sexual Prowess: Successfully attracting sexual partners can be seen as a measure of masculinity (Connell & Messerschmidt, 2015). For example, fictional characters like James Bond are portrayed as overwhelmingly attractive to women.
Competitiveness: Often, masculinity is associated with the need to compete and win (Bridges & Pascoe, 2014). Corporate leaders like Elon Musk and his competition with other billionaires in the space industry exemplify this.
Dominance: Exerting control in social situations is often seen as a masculine trait (Kimmel & Aronson, 2011). This can be seen in team leaders, such as football captains, who direct and guide their team.
Stoicism: Preserving composure in the face of adversity is considered a masculine virtue (Connell & Messerschmidt, 2015). For example, firefighters remaining calm in dangerous situations.
Financial Independence: Masculinity is often associated with earning power and economic independence (Bridges & Pascoe, 2014). Successful businessmen like Warren Buffett exemplify this trait.
Authority: Men who wield authority, either at home or at work, are often seen as embodying masculinity (Kimmel & Aronson, 2011). Historic world leaders, such as Winston Churchill, can serve as examples.
Autonomy: Emphasizing self-reliance and independence is a commonly upheld masculine trait (Connell & Messerschmidt, 2015). Backpackers traveling alone through challenging terrains embody this characteristic.
Risk-Taking: Men are often expected to be adventurous and willing to confront danger (Bridges & Pascoe, 2014). This trait can be seen in adrenaline pursuits such as skydiving or bungee jumping.
See More Masculinity Examples Here
Femininity
Femininity, fundamentally, characterizes traits, roles, and behaviors typically associated with women in a given society (Brown & Gilligan, 2013).
Traits associated with femininity often include nurturing, empathy, sensitivity, and non-aggressive communication.
As with masculinity, the construct of femininity extends beyond women, as men can, and often do, embody these traits.
Examining femininity critically, it is often linked to the private sphere and associated with the nurturing and caring roles (Lemon, 2016).
These expectations are often structured around homemaking, child-rearing, and other forms of emotional labor.
An example of this expectation might be a character like Marmee March in “Little Women,” who embodies the loving, nurturing, and domestic qualities associated with traditional ideas of femininity.
Contrary to past stereotypical portrayals, modern understandings of femininity acknowledge its complex and diverse nature (Brown & Gilligan, 2013). Femininity is not monolithic; instead, it intersects with other identity aspects such as race, socioeconomic status, and sexual orientation, leading to varying expressions and experiences.
A contemporary portrayal of femininity may include a Fortune 500 CEO who leads with compassion and empathy, effectively blending traits typically associated with both femininity and masculinity.
This underscores the emergence of a more fluid understanding of femininity that resists binary categorizations.
Femininity Examples
The following are traits traditionally associated with femininity. Please note that these are generalized, traditional, and often outdated stereotypes, and do not necessarily apply to every individual:
Emotional Openness: Women are typically expected to be more open with their emotions (Brown & Gilligan, 2013). A well-known movie character who embodies this would be Julia Roberts’ character in ‘Steel Magnolias’, who readily shares her feelings with those around her.
Nurturing Behavior: Femininity is often associated with nurturing and caring for others (Lemon, 2016). An example can be seen in the role of Florence Nightingale, historically known for her caring nature and dedication to nursing.
Empathy: Empathy, or the understanding and sharing of others’ feelings, is traditionally seen as a feminine trait. A famous example could be Mother Teresa and her profound empathy for the less fortunate.
Verbal Communication: Women are often associated with verbal skills and are often expected to be conversationally engaging (Brown & Gilligan, 2013). Oprah Winfrey, a noted television host and interviewer, is an example who uses these skills masterfully.
Cooperation: Societal expectations often associate femininity with cooperative and collaborative work. An example could be seen in team projects in any professional setting where female team members work constructively to reach a common goal.
Modesty: Cultural norms often link modesty, or humility, with femininity. For instance, Aung San Suu Kyi is often praised for her modest approach in leading her political movement.
Concern for Appearance: Attention to personal grooming and appearance is often associated with femininity. One real-world example is the flourishing beauty and fashion industry largely catering to women.
Flexibility: Adaptability and flexibility, especially emotional, are commonly viewed as feminine traits (Lemon, 2016). An example is evident in many working mothers who juggle multiplicity of roles and adapt to changing circumstances.
Patience: Historically, patience has often been hailed as a feminine virtue. An example could be a teacher like Maria Montessori, who demonstrated patience in her innovative approach to education.
Gracefulness: Gracefulness, such as in movement, manners, or style, is often ascribed to femininity. Many female dancers, like Misty Copeland, embody this trait through their performances.
See More Femininity Examples Here
Table of Differences Between Femininity and Masculinity
MasculinityFemininityTypical Gender StereotypesStrong, assertive, independent, competitive, emotionally reserved.Gentle, nurturing, cooperative, sensitive, emotionally expressive.Roles in Society (traditional view)Expected to be providers, protectors, leaders, decision-makers.Expected to be caregivers, supporters, followers, empathetic listeners.Emotional ExpressionTraditionally discouraged from showing emotions (except anger). Often told to “man up”.Encouraged to express emotions freely. Associated with empathy and compassion.CommunicationDirect, assertive. Prefers to solve problems independently.Indirect, cooperative. Prefers collaboration and discussion.Occupations (traditional view)Careers in politics, science, engineering, military, business.Careers in nursing, teaching, social work, fashion, beauty.Relationship to PowerMore likely to seek power, assert dominance, and take up space.Traditionally less likely to seek power, often adopting supportive or subordinate roles.Physical Appearance (traditional view)Muscular, tall, short hair, less emphasis on clothing and accessories.Soft, petite, long hair, more emphasis on clothing, makeup, and accessories.
This table reflects traditional views on masculinity and femininity. It is important to understand that individuals may identify with traits from both columns or none at all, and that’s perfectly okay.
It’s also crucial to recognize that societal views on gender are changing, with many societies moving towards more fluid understandings of gender roles and characteristics.
Cultural Variations in Masculine and Feminine Stereotypes
Cultural differences in gender norms play a significant role in shaping perceptions of masculinity and femininity (Connell & Messerschmidt, 2015). In fact, some cultures even have multiple different types of genders.
Essentially, what is considered masculine or feminine can vary greatly from one culture to another. Such cultural ideals are deeply embedded and shape individual behavior, identities, and societal norms at large.
In some societies, the concept of masculinity is strictly tied to physical strength, stoicism, and economic prowess (Maass et al., 2016). For instance, in many traditional societies, manual labor and physical strength define a man’s masculinity.
On the contrary, in other societies, mental strength, emotional intelligence, and the ability to provide for the family define masculinity. An example might be the difference in expression of masculinity between the Maasai warriors of Kenya, whose rites of passage include lion hunting, and men in Scandinavian cultures, where gender equality and shared household work is emphasized.
Femininity, as well, can exhibit significant cultural variation.
In some cultures, femininity is tied to domesticity, gentleness, and passivity (Maass et al., 2016). For instance, in many fundamentalist and deeply conservative societies, women’s roles are traditionally restricted to the private sphere: homemaking, child-rearing, etc.
However, in other cultures, femininity can also be associated with strength, leadership, and independence. The Mosuo culture in China, for instance, is a matrilineal society where women are heads of households, and their economic and social status are more prominent, challenging traditional notions of femininity.
See Also: 10 Types of Masculinity
Conclusion
Masculinity and femininity are fluid constructs, molded by cultural norms, values, and historical contexts. Therefore, they are subject to continuous change and redefinition.
References
Basow, S. A. (1992). Gender: Stereotypes and roles. Thomson Brooks/Cole Publishing Co.
Bridges, T., & Pascoe, C. J. (2014). Exploring masculinities: Identity, inequality, continuity, and change. Oxford University Press.
Brown, L. M., & Gilligan, C. (2013). Meeting at the Crossroads: Women’s Psychology and Girls’ Development. Harvard University Press. Doi: https://doi.org/10.1176/ajp.151.2.281
Connell, R., & Messerschmidt, J. (2015). Hegemonic masculinity: Rethinking the concept. Gender & Society, 19(6), 829-859. Doi: https://doi.org/10.1177/0891243205278639
Kimmel, M., & Aronson, A. (2011). The gendered society. Oxford University Press.
Lemon, R. (2016). “Femininity” as a Barrier to Positive Sexual Health for Adolescent Girls. Journal of Adolescent Health, 59(2), 154-159.
Maass, V. S., Cadinu, M., Guarnieri, G., & Grasselli, A. (2016). Sexual harassment under social identity threat: The computer harassment paradigm. Journal of Personality & Social Psychology, 75(5), 1245–1261. Doi: https://psycnet.apa.org/doi/10.1037/0022-3514.85.5.853
O’Neil, M. (2013). Men’s and Women’s Gender Role Journeys: Metaphor for Healing, Transition, and Transformation. Springer Publishing Company.
Chris Drew (PhD)
Website
|
+ posts
Dr. Chris Drew is the founder of the Helpful Professor. He holds a PhD in education and has published over 20 articles in scholarly journals. He is the former editor of the Journal of Learning Development in Higher Education. [Image Descriptor: Photo of Chris]
Chris Drew (PhD)
https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/
50 Durable Goods Examples
Chris Drew (PhD)
https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/
100 Consumer Goods Examples
Chris Drew (PhD)
https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/
30 Globalization Pros and Cons
Chris Drew (PhD)
https://helpfulprofessor.com/author/chris-drew-phd/
17 Adversity Examples (And How to Overcome Them)
Leave a Comment Cancel ReplyYour email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *Type here..Name*
Email*
Website
This Article was Last Expert Reviewed on October 18, 2023 by Chris Drew, PhD
We cite peer reviewed academic articles wherever possible and reference our sources at the end of our articles. All articles are edited by a PhD level academic. Learn more about our academic and editorial standards.Cite this Article in your Essay (APA Style)Drew, C. (July 13, 2023). Masculinity vs Femininity: Similarities and Differences. Helpful Professor. https://helpfulprofessor.com/masculinity-vs-femininity/Search for a Study GuideSearchReady to Write your Essay? I'll Help you get Started:
My 5 Paragraph Intro Method
How to Start your Essay
How to Paraphrase Like a Pro
My 5 C's Conclusions Method
How to Edit your Essay for 13% Higher Grades
How to Overcome Study Procrastination
Privacy PolicyTerms and ConditionsDisclaimerAccessibility Statement
As an Amazon Associate I earn from qualifying purchases.
About The Helpful Professor®
Copyright © 2024 Helpful ProfessorHelpful Professor® is a USPTO Registered TrademarkAll the advice on this site is general in nature. Seekprofessional input on your specific circumstances. Studentsshould always cross-check any information on this site with their course teacher.
Femininity and Masculinity - Sociology of Gender - iResearchNet
Femininity and Masculinity - Sociology of Gender - iResearchNet
Skip to main content Skip to primary sidebarCustom Writing Services
How to Write a Research Paper
Research Paper Topics
Research Paper Examples
Order
SociologyIResearchNetAcademic Writing Services
Sociology » Sociology of Gender » Femininity and MasculinityFemininity and Masculinity
Femininity and masculinity are acquired social identities: as individuals become socialized they develop a gender identity, an understanding of what it means to be a ‘‘man’’ or a ‘‘woman’’ (Laurie et al. 1999). How individuals develop an understanding of their gender identity, including whether or not they fit into these prescribed gender roles, depends upon the context within which they are socialized and how they view themselves in relation to societal gender norms. Class, racial, ethnic, and national factors play heavily into how individuals construct their gender identities and how they are perceived externally (hooks 2004). Gender identities are often naturalized; that is, they rely on a notion of biological difference, ‘‘so that ‘natural’ femininity [in a white, European, middle class context] encompasses, for example, motherhood, being nurturing, a desire for pretty clothes and the exhibition of emotions’’ (Laurie et al. 1999: 3). ‘‘Natural’’ masculinity, in contrast, may encompass fatherhood, acting ‘‘tough,’’ a desire for sports and competition, and hiding emotions (Connell 1997; Thompson 2000). In both cases, these constructions of gender identity are based on stereotypes that fall within the range of normative femininities and masculinities. Yet, as many sociologists have pointed out, not all individuals fit within these prescribed norms and as such, masculinities and femininities must be recognized as socially constituted, fluid, wide ranging, and historically and geographically differentiated (Connell 1997; Halberstam 1998; Laurie et al. 1999).
Feminist scholars have long addressed the social construction of femininities, particularly in the context of gender inequality and power (Lorber 1994). Early second wave feminist scholars such as Simone de Beauvoir (1980) argued that women’s subordinated status in western societies was due to socialization rather than to any essential biological gender difference, as evidenced in her often cited phrase, ‘‘One is not born, but rather becomes, a woman.’’ Many feminist scholars in Anglo Saxon and European countries have emphasized social construction over biological difference as an explanation for women’s ways of being, acting, and knowing in the world and for their related gender subordination (Gilligan 1993). Some feminist scholars have addressed the social construction of femininities as a way to explain wage inequality, the global ‘‘feminization of poverty,’’ and women’s relegation to ‘‘feminine’’ labor markets (e.g., secretarial labor, garment industry, caring labor) and to the so called private realm of the household and family (Folbre 2001). Because feminists were primarily concerned with the question of women’s subordination, masculinities themselves were rarely analyzed except in cases where scholars sought an explanation for male aggression or power. Likewise, hegemonic femininity was emphasized over alternative femininities such that the experiences of women who did not fit into socially prescribed gender roles were either left unexamined or viewed through the normative lens of gender dualisms (Halberstam 1998).
Particularly since the 1980s, at least three areas of research on gender identity have helped shift the debate on femininities and masculinities: (1) masculinity studies, which emerged primarily in the 1980s and 1990s; (2) queer studies and lesbian, gay, bisexual, and transgender (LGBT) studies, including the pivotal research of Butler (1990); and (3) gender, race, ethnic, and postcolonial studies, a trajectory of scholarship in which researchers have long critiqued hegemonic forms of masculinity and femininity on the basis that these racialized constructions helped reinforce the criminalization and subordination of racial/ethnic minorities in industrialized societies and the colonization of both men and women in poor and/or nonwestern regions.
In contrast to feminist scholarship that focused primarily on women’s experiences with femininity, Connell’s (1987) research on ‘‘hegemonic masculinity and emphasized femininity’’ was among the first to systematically analyze both sets of constructions as they contribute to global gender inequality. Connell argues ‘‘hegemonic masculinity,’’ a type of masculinity oriented toward accommodating the interests and desires of men, forms the basis of patriarchal social orders. Similarly, ‘‘emphasized femininity,’’ a hegemonic form of femininity, is ‘‘defined around compliance with [female] sub ordination and is oriented to accommodating the interests and desires of men’’ (p. 23). Borrowing from Gramsci’s analysis of class hegemony and struggle, Connell develops a framework for understanding multiple competing masculinities and femininities. He argues that hegemonic masculinity is always constructed in relation to various subordinated masculinities as well as in relation to women. Thus, for example, non-European, poor, non-white, and/or gay men tend to experience subordinated masculinities, whereas men of middle class European, white, and/or heterosexual backgrounds tend to benefit from the privileges of hegemonic masculinity.
Especially since the 1980s, scholars of masculinity studies have produced innovative research on various aspects of men’s lives and experiences. Messner (1992), for example, examines men’s identifications with sports as an example of how masculinities are constructed and maintained. Messner analyzes the ‘‘male viewer’’ of today’s most popular spectator sports in terms of the mythology and symbolism of masculine identification: common themes he encounters in his research include patriotism, militarism, violence, and meritocracy. Scholars of gay masculinities have addressed how gay men of various ethnic, racial, class, and national backgrounds have negotiated hegemonic masculinity, sometimes in contradictory ways, and constructed alternative masculinities through their everyday lives (Messner 1997).
Importantly, research on hegemonic masculinities sheds light on how and why masculinity has been largely ‘‘invisible’’ in the lives of men who benefit from hegemonic masculinity and in the field of women’s/gender studies, which tends to focus on the experiences of women. Although there are obvious reasons why the field of women’s/gender studies has focused primarily on women, since women experience gender inequalities more than men, scholars increasingly have pointed out that male socialization processes and identities, as well as masculinist institutions and theories, should be examined as a way to rethink gender inequality. As Kimmel (2002) notes: ‘‘The ‘invisibility’ of masculinity in discussions of [gender] has political dimensions. The processes that confer privilege on one group and not another group are often invisible to those upon whom that privilege is conferred. Thus, not having to think about race is one of the luxuries of being white, just as not having to think about gender is one of the ‘patriarchal dividends’ of gender inequality.’’
Judith Butler’s research on gender performativity has opened space for discussion about the naturalized linking of gender identity, the body, and sexual desire. Butler (1990) argues feminism has made a mistake by trying to assert that ‘‘women’’ are a group with common characteristics and interests. Like socio biologists, feminists who rely exclusively on a sociocultural explanation of gender identity construction also fall prey to essentialism. Many individuals, especially those who define as ‘‘queer’’ or as lesbian, gay, bisexual, or trans gendered, do not experience gender identity, embodiment, and sexual desire through the dominant norms of gender and heterosexuality. Influenced by Foucault, Butler suggests, like Connell, that certain cultural configurations of gender have seized a hegemonic hold. She calls for subversive action in the present: ‘‘gender trouble,’’ the mobilization, subversive confusion, and proliferation of genders, and therefore identity. This idea of identity as free floating and not connected to an ‘‘essence’’ is one of the key ideas expressed in queer theory (EGS 2005).
Butler and other queer theorists have addressed how normative femininities and masculinities play a role in disciplining the lives of LGBT individuals. Halberstam’s (1998) research addresses constructions of ‘‘female masculinity’’ and argues that scholars must separate discussions of gender identity (e.g., masculinities, femininities) from discussions of the body. Women can ‘‘act masculine’’ just as men can ‘‘act feminine’’; how individuals identify in terms of their gender is not and should not be linked to their biological anatomies, however defined. Halberstam’s own research addresses how masculine identified women experience gender, the stratification of masculinities (e.g., ‘‘heroic’’ vs. alternative masculinities), and the public emergence of other genders. Other scholars have examined how medical and scientific institutions have managed normative gender (and sexual) identities through psychological protocols and surgical intervention (Fausto Sterling 2000). This type of research points toward a broader understanding of gender that places dualistic conceptions of ‘‘masculine’’ vs. ‘‘feminine’’ and ‘‘male’’ vs. ‘‘female’’ into question.
Scholars of race, ethnic, and postcolonial studies have addressed how normative femininities and masculinities, which tend to benefit those with racial/ethnic privilege, help rein force a racialized social order in which subordinated groups are demasculinized or feminized in ways that maintain their racial/ethnic sub ordination in society. One example involves the stereotyping of African American men as unruly and hypersexual. The ‘‘myth of the male rapist,’’ as Davis (2001) has discussed, has played a highly destructive role in black men’s lives and has influenced legal, political, and social actions toward them, including their disproportionate criminalization for rape, often based on fraudulent charges. Another example concerns immigrant men racialized as minorities in the US. Thai (2002) illustrates how working class Vietnamese American men have developed innovative strategies to achieve higher status in their communities by marrying middle to upper class Vietnamese women and bringing them to the US. Faced with few marriage options and low paying jobs in the US, working class Vietnamese American men who experience a form of subordinated masculinity seek upward mobility through these transnational marriage networks.
Women of color in the US and working class women in developing countries also face unequal access to hegemonic femininity, as defined in western terms. Hill Collins (2004) addresses how African American women have been hypersexualized in US popular culture, thereby placing them outside the realm of normative femininity according to hegemonic white, western standards. Postcolonial studies scholars have demonstrated how poor women in developing regions (particularly non-white women) have been sexualized by male tourists from industrialized countries and sometimes also by local men (Freeman 2001). More broadly, scholars of masculinities and/or femininities have pointed out how constructions of masculinities and femininities are embedded in social institutions (e.g., the state, economy, nation, educational system) and processes (e.g., social welfare policy, globalization, colonization, political campaigns, popular culture, everyday life) and shape individuals’ everyday experiences and gendered self-perceptions (Connell 1987, 1997; Laurie et al. 1999; Free man 2001; Hill Collins 2004).
Critics have defended normative femininity and masculinity on religious, moral, and/or biological grounds. Some, for example, have argued that these social norms (what Connell would call hegemonic masculinity and emphasized femininity) are ‘‘naturally’’ aligned with men’s and women’s assumed biological roles in reproduction and/or with their assumed heterosexual desire (see Lorber 1994; Messner 1997). On all sides of the ideological spectrum, individuals have participated in interesting political responses and social movements that either embrace or challenge dominant societal constructions of masculinity and femininity. Some women have joined feminist movements and challenged traditional notions of femininity; whereas other women have joined right wing women’s movements that embrace
traditional gender roles and identities (e.g., Concerned Women for America). Men have formed feminist men’s movements, based largely on the principles of women’s feminist movements, as well as movements to embrace traditional notions of fatherhood, as in the divergent examples of the Christian based (and largely white, middle class) Promise Keepers and the Million Man Marches, first organized in 1995 by Nation of Islam leader Louis Farrakhan and attended by over 800,000 African American men as part of a movement to reclaim black masculinity (Messner 1997).
Future research on femininities and masculinities will likely be influenced by the recent scholarship in the fields of masculinity studies, queer theory and LGBT studies, and race, ethnic, and postcolonial studies. Although scholars vary in their disciplinary backgrounds and methodological approaches to the study of femininities and masculinities, most would agree that femininities and masculinities can be seen as sets of rules or norms that govern female and male behavior, appearance, and self-image
References:
Butler, (1990) Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Subversion of Identity. Routledge, New York.
Connell, W. (1987) Gender and Power: Society, the Person and Sexual Politics. Stanford University Press, Palo Alto.
Connell, W. (1997) Hegemonic Masculinity and Emphasized Femininity. In: Richardson, L., Taylor, V., & Whittier, N. (Eds.), Feminist Frontiers IV. McGraw-Hill, New York, pp. 22-5.
Davis, (2001) Rape, Racism and the Myth of the Black Rapist. In: Bhavnani, K.-K. (Ed.), Feminism and ‘‘Race.’’ Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp. 50-64.
de Beauvoir, (1980 [1952]) The Second Sex. Random House/Alfred Knopf, New York.
European Graduate School (EGS) (2005) Judith Online. http://egs.edu/faculty/judith-butler.
Fausto-Sterling, (2000) Sexing the Body: Gender Politics and the Construction of Sexuality. Basic Books, New York.
Folbre, (2001) The Invisible Heart: Economics and Family Values. New Press, New York.
Freeman, (2001) Is Local : Global as Feminine : Masculine? Rethinking the Gender of Globalization. Signs 26(4): 1007-38.
Gilligan, (1993) In A Different Voice: Psychological Theory and Women’s Development. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA.
Halberstam, (1998) Female Masculinity. Duke University Press, Durham, NC.
Hill Collins, P. (2004) Black Sexual Politics: African Americans, Gender, and the New Racism. Routledge, New
hooks, b. (2004) We Real Cool: Black Men and Masculinity. Routledge, New
Kimmel, (2002) Foreword. In: Cleaver, F. (Ed.), Masculinities Matter! Men, Gender and Development. Zed Books, London, pp. xi xiv.
Laurie, , Dwyer, C., Holloway, S., & Smith, F. (1999) Geographies of New Femininities. Longman, London.
Lorber, (1994) Paradoxes of Gender. Yale University Press, New Haven.
Messner, A. (1992) Power at Play. Beacon Press, Boston.
Messner, A. (1997) Politics in Masculinities: Men in Movements. Sage, Walnut Creek, CA.
Thai, C. (2002) Clashing Dreams: Highly Educated Overseas Brides and Low-Wage US Husbands. In: Ehrenreich, B. & Hochschild, A. R. (Eds.), Global Woman: Nannies, Maids, and Sex Workers in the New Economy. Metropolitan Books, New York, pp. 230-53.
Thompson, C. (2000) The Male Role Stereotype. In: Cyrus, V. (Ed.), Experiencing Race, Class, and Gender in the United States. Mayfield Publishing, Mountain View, CA, pp. 85-7.
Back to Sociology of Gender
Primary SidebarFacebookGitHubInstagramPinterestTwitterYouTube
Search the site ...
Sociology Research
Sociology of GenderGender Definition in SociologyDoing GenderFemale MasculinityFemininity and MasculinityGender and AgingGender and ConsumptionGender and DevelopmentGender and DevianceGender and EducationGender and FriendshipGender and HealthGender and Social MovementsGender and the BodyGender BiasGender Division of LaborGender IdeologyGender MainstreamingGender, Work, and FamilyGendered EnterpriseGendered OrganizationsHegemonic MasculinityMatrix of DominationPatriarchyRacialized GenderRepressive HypothesisTransgender, Transvestism, and TranssexualismWomanismWomen’s Empowerment
Custom Writing Services
Femininity Definition & Meaning - Merriam-Webster
Femininity Definition & Meaning - Merriam-Webster
Menu Toggle
Merriam-Webster Logo
Games & Quizzes
Games & Quizzes
Word of the Day
Grammar
Wordplay
Word Finder
Thesaurus
Join MWU
Shop
Books
Merch
Settings
My Words
Recents
Account
Log Out
More
Thesaurus
Join MWU
Shop
Books
Merch
Log In
Username
My Words
Recents
Account
Log Out
Est. 1828
Dictionary
Definition
Definition
Synonyms
Example Sentences
Word History
Phrases Containing
Entries Near
Cite this EntryCitation
Share
Medical DefinitionMedical
More from M-W
Show more
Show more
Citation
Share
Medical
More from M-W
Save Word
To save this word, you'll need to log in.
Log In
femininity
noun
fem·i·nin·i·ty
ˌfe-mə-ˈni-nə-tē
Synonyms of femininity
1
: the quality or nature of the female sex : the quality, state, or degree of being feminine or womanly
challenging traditional notions about femininity and masculinity … the women were visions of powerful femininity.—Alan Shipnuck
2
: woman, womankind
… he was now to contrast her sharply with the best of what the Old World had to offer in the matter of femininity …—Theodore Dreiser
Synonyms
feminity
muliebrity
womanhood
womanishness
womanliness
See all Synonyms & Antonyms in Thesaurus
Examples of femininity in a Sentence
Recent Examples on the Web
Her sturdiness works its way into her performances onscreen: Even in many a period drama, Winslet, for all her femininity, conveys the impression of someone who could hold her own in a street fight.
—Susan Dominus, New York Times, 3 Mar. 2024
The result is sleek and fluid, with a dose of romantic femininity.
—Christina Holevas, Vogue, 15 Feb. 2024
The Shōgun model of femininity, according to which the women are ostensibly subservient but capable of triggering pivotal upheavals, offers juicy material for Hoshi, heartbreaking and unreadable, and Nikaido, who makes her character manipulative and fiercely maternal.
—Daniel Fienberg, The Hollywood Reporter, 12 Feb. 2024
Perhaps what’s missing is an essential element of your femininity and the foundation of your spiritual ecosystem: Sensuality.
—Essence, 10 Jan. 2024
Bandit grew up with the idea that femininity meant fashion, spangles, performance.
—Rachel Monroe, The New Yorker, 6 Dec. 2023
In a pop field that’s often dominated by femininity, Newham purposefully embraces their gender fluidity, combining Eighties Jazzercise choreography with David Byrne-esque suiting and sharp lines.
—Ct Jones, Rolling Stone, 28 Nov. 2023
Feminist women despise femininity (i.e. motherhood) according to Chesterton's observations 100 years ago.
—Michael Brendan Dougherty, National Review, 10 Nov. 2023
Its balconette design and demi-bra cups provide just the right amount of support and femininity while keeping you comfortable thanks to its mesh material.
—Alyssa Brascia, Peoplemag, 10 Feb. 2024
See More
These examples are programmatically compiled from various online sources to illustrate current usage of the word 'femininity.' Any opinions expressed in the examples do not represent those of Merriam-Webster or its editors. Send us feedback about these examples.
Word History
First Known Use
14th century, in the meaning defined at sense 1
Time Traveler
The first known use of femininity was
in the 14th century
See more words from the same century
Phrases Containing femininity
hyper-femininity
Dictionary Entries Near femininity
feminine rhyme
femininity
feminise
See More Nearby Entries
Cite this Entry
Style
MLA
Chicago
APA
Merriam-Webster
“Femininity.” Merriam-Webster.com Dictionary, Merriam-Webster, https://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/femininity. Accessed 12 Mar. 2024.
Copy Citation
Share
Post the Definition of femininity to Facebook
Share the Definition of femininity on Twitter
Medical Definition
femininity
noun
fem·i·nin·i·ty
ˌfem-ə-ˈnin-ət-ē
plural femininities
: the quality or nature of the female sex
More from Merriam-Webster on femininity
Nglish: Translation of femininity for Spanish Speakers
Britannica English: Translation of femininity for Arabic Speakers
Last Updated:
8 Mar 2024
- Updated example sentences
Love words? Need even more definitions?
Subscribe to America's largest dictionary and get thousands more definitions and advanced search—ad free!
Merriam-Webster unabridged
Can you solve 4 words at once?
Play
Play
Can you solve 4 words at once?
Play
Play
Word of the Day
ulterior
See Definitions and Examples »
Get Word of the Day daily email!
Popular in Grammar & Usage
See All
8 Grammar Terms You Used to Know, But Forgot
Homophones, Homographs, and Homonyms
Your vs. You're: How to Use Them Correctly
Every Letter Is Silent, Sometimes: A-Z List of Examples
More Commonly Mispronounced Words
See All
Popular in Wordplay
See All
'Arsy-Varsy,' and Other Snappy Reduplicatives
The Words of the Week - Mar. 8
10 Scrabble Words Without Any Vowels
12 More Bird Names that Sound Like Insults (and Sometimes Are)
8 Uncommon Words Related to Love
See All
Games & Quizzes
See All
Quordle
Can you solve 4 words at once?
Play
Blossom Word Game
You can make only 12 words. Pick the best ones!
Play
Missing Letter
A crossword with a twist
Play
Spelling Bee Quiz
Can you outdo past winners of the National Spelli...
Take the quiz
Merriam Webster
Learn a new word every day. Delivered to your inbox!
Help
About Us
Advertising Info
Contact Us
Diversity
Privacy Policy
Terms of Use
YouTube
© 2024 Merriam-Webster, Incorporated
Femininity | SpringerLink
Femininity | SpringerLink
Skip to main content
Advertisement
Log in
Menu
Find a journal
Publish with us
Track your research
Search
Cart
Encyclopedia of Personality and Individual Differences pp 1584–1588Cite as
Home
Encyclopedia of Personality and Individual Differences
Reference work entry
Femininity
Clare M. Mehta3 & Victoria Henry4
Reference work entry
First Online: 01 January 2020
189 Accesses
Synonyms
Femaleness; Womanhood; Womanishness; Womanliness
Definition
The term femininity is generally used to refer to a set of socialized psychological traits, qualities, and attributes most closely associated with those whose birth assigned gender category is female. Feminine traits and attributes include passivity, submissiveness, gentleness, warmth, helpfulness, compassion, understanding, dependency, emotional expressiveness, and the presence of maternal instinct. These feminine traits have been described as communal traits or a relational orientation. Consequently, an important component of femininity is connecting with, helping and caring for others. Defined in this way, femininity seems to be a straight forward concept, however, it is far more complicated – and potentially problematic – than it first appears. The complexity of femininity is explored in more detail below.
Although femininity and its antonym masculinity are often linked to birth assigned gender categories, it is...
This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.
Buying options
Chapter
EUR 29.95
Price includes VAT (Philippines)
Available as PDF
Read on any device
Instant download
Own it forever
Buy Chapter
eBook
EUR 3,209.99
Price includes VAT (Philippines)
Available as EPUB and PDF
Read on any device
Instant download
Own it forever
Buy eBook
Hardcover Book
EUR 4,499.99
Price excludes VAT (Philippines)
Durable hardcover edition
Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
Free shipping worldwide - see info
Buy Hardcover Book
Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout
Purchases are for personal use onlyLearn about institutional subscriptions
ReferencesBem, S. L. (1974). The measurement of psychological androgyny. Journal of Consulting and Clinical Psychology, 42, 155–162. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0036215.Article
PubMed
Google Scholar
Bem, S. L. (1981). Gender schema theory: A cognitive account of sex typing. Psychological Review, 88, 354–364. doi: 0033-295X/81/8804-0354$00.75.
Google Scholar
Bosson, J. K., & Michniewicz, K. S. (2013). Gender dichotomization at the level of ingroup identity: What it is, and why men use it more than women. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 105, 425–442. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0033126.Article
PubMed
Google Scholar
Butler, J. (2004). Undoing gender. New York: Routledge.Book
Google Scholar
Connell, R. W., & Messerschmidt, J. W. (2005). Hegemonic masculinity: Rethinking the concept. Gender & Society, 19, 829–859. https://doi.org/10.1177/0891243205278639.Article
Google Scholar
Constantinople, A. (1973). Masculinity-femininity: An exception to a famous dictum? Psychological Bulletin, 80, 389–407. https://doi.org/10.1037/h0035334.Article
PubMed
Google Scholar
Deaux, K., & Major, B. (1987). Putting gender into context: An interactive model of gender-related behavior. Psychological Review, 94, 369–389. https://doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.94.3.369.Article
Google Scholar
Gaughan, M. (2006). The gender structure of adolescent peer influence on drinking. Journal of Health & Social Behavior, 47, 47–61.Article
Google Scholar
Hyde, J. S. (2005). The gender similarities hypothesis. American Psychologist, 60, 581–592.Article
Google Scholar
Joel, D., Berman, Z., Tavor, I., Wexler, N., Gaber, O., Stein, Y., & … Assaf, Y. (2015). Sex beyond the genitalia: The human brain mosaic. Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 112(50), 15468–15473. https://doi.org/10.1073/pnas.1509654112.Keener, E. (2015). The complexity of gender: It is all that and more….In sum, it is complicated. Sex Roles. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11199-015-0542-5.Article
Google Scholar
Leszczynski, J. P., & Strough, J. (2008). The contextual specificity of masculinity and femininity in early adolescence. Social Development, 17, 719–736. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-9507.2007.00443.x.Article
Google Scholar
Maccoby, E. E. (1990). Gender and relationships: A developmental account. American Psychologist, 45(4), 513.Article
Google Scholar
Martin, H., & Finn, S. E. (2010). Masculinity and femininity in the MMPI-2 and MMPI-A. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
Google Scholar
Mehta, C. M. (2015). Gender in context: Considering variability in wood and Eagly’s traditions of gender identity. Sex Roles, 73, 490–496. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11199-015-0535-4.Article
Google Scholar
Mehta, C.M. & Dementieva, Y. (2016). The contextual specificity of gender: Femininity and masculinity in college students’ same- and other-gender peer contexts. Sex Roles, Advance online publication. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11199-016-0632-z.Mehta, C. M., & Strough, J. (2009). Sex segregation in friendships and normative contexts across the life span. Developmental Review, 29, 201–220. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.dr.2009.06.001.Article
Google Scholar
Pascoe, C. J. (2005). ‘dude, you’re a fag’: Adolescent masculinity and the fag discourse. Sexualities, 8, 329–346.Article
Google Scholar
Pickard, J., & Strough, J. (2003). The effects of same-sex and other-sex contexts on masculinity and femininity. Sex Roles, 48, 421–432. https://doi.org/10.1037/t00748-000.Article
Google Scholar
Pleck, J. H. (1981). The myth of masculinity. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Google Scholar
Ridgeway, C., Johnson, C., & Diekema, D. (1994). External status, legitimacy, and compliance in male and female groups. Social Forces, 72, 1051–1077.Article
Google Scholar
Smiler, A. P. (2004). Thirty years after the discovery of gender: Psychological concepts and measures of masculinity. Sex Roles, 50(1–2), 15–26. https://doi.org/10.1023/B:SERS.0000011069.02279.4c.Article
Google Scholar
Strough, J., Leszczynski, J., Neely, T. L., Flinn, J. A., & Margrett, J. (2007). From adolescence to later adulthood: Femininity, masculinity, and androgyny in six age groups. Sex Roles, 57(5–6), 385–396. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11199-007-9282-5.Article
Google Scholar
Terman, L. M., & Miles, C. C. (1936). Sex and personality: Studies in masculinity and femininity. New York: McGraw-Hill Book Company.Book
Google Scholar
Tobin, D. D., Menon, M., Menon, M., Spatta, B. C., Hodges, E. E., & Perry, D. G. (2010). The intrapsychics of gender: A model of self-socialization. Psychological Review, 117, 601–622. https://doi.org/10.1037/a0018936.Article
PubMed
Google Scholar
Wade, J. C. (2008). Masculinity ideology, male reference group identity dependence, and African American men’s health-related attitudes and behaviors. Psychology of Men & Masculinity, 9, 5–16. https://doi.org/10.1037/1524-9220.9.1.5.Article
Google Scholar
Watzlawik, M. (2009). When a man thinks he has female traits constructing femininity and masculinity: Methodological potentials and limitations. Integrative Psychological & Behavioral Science, 43, 126–137. https://doi.org/10.1007/s12124-008-9085-4.Article
Google Scholar
West, C., & Zimmerman, D. H. (1987). Doing gender. Gender & Society, 1, 125–151. https://doi.org/10.1177/0891243287001002002.Article
Google Scholar
Wood, W., & Eagly, A. H. (2015). Two traditions of research on gender identity. Sex Roles, 73, 461–473. https://doi.org/10.1007/s11199-015-0480-2.Article
Google Scholar
Download referencesAuthor informationAuthors and AffiliationsBoston Children’s Hospital, Emmanuel College, Boston, MA, USAClare M. MehtaEmmanuel College, Boston, MA, USAVictoria HenryAuthorsClare M. MehtaView author publicationsYou can also search for this author in
PubMed Google ScholarVictoria HenryView author publicationsYou can also search for this author in
PubMed Google ScholarCorresponding authorCorrespondence to
Clare M. Mehta .Editor informationEditors and AffiliationsOakland University, Rochester, MI, USAVirgil Zeigler-Hill Oakland University, Rochester, MI, USATodd K. Shackelford Section Editor informationLakehead University, Orillia, ON, CanadaBeth A. VisserRights and permissionsReprints and permissionsCopyright information© 2020 Springer Nature Switzerland AGAbout this entryCite this entryMehta, C.M., Henry, V. (2020). Femininity.
In: Zeigler-Hill, V., Shackelford, T.K. (eds) Encyclopedia of Personality and Individual Differences. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-24612-3_1076Download citation.RIS.ENW.BIBDOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-24612-3_1076Published: 22 April 2020
Publisher Name: Springer, Cham
Print ISBN: 978-3-319-24610-9
Online ISBN: 978-3-319-24612-3eBook Packages: Behavioral Science and PsychologyReference Module Humanities and Social SciencesReference Module Business, Economics and Social SciencesShare this entryAnyone you share the following link with will be able to read this content:Get shareable linkSorry, a shareable link is not currently available for this article.Copy to clipboard
Provided by the Springer Nature SharedIt content-sharing initiative
Publish with usPolicies and ethics
Access via your institution
Buying options
Chapter
EUR 29.95
Price includes VAT (Philippines)
Available as PDF
Read on any device
Instant download
Own it forever
Buy Chapter
eBook
EUR 3,209.99
Price includes VAT (Philippines)
Available as EPUB and PDF
Read on any device
Instant download
Own it forever
Buy eBook
Hardcover Book
EUR 4,499.99
Price excludes VAT (Philippines)
Durable hardcover edition
Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
Free shipping worldwide - see info
Buy Hardcover Book
Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout
Purchases are for personal use onlyLearn about institutional subscriptions
Search
Search by keyword or author
Search
Navigation
Find a journal
Publish with us
Track your research
Discover content
Journals A-Z
Books A-Z
Publish with us
Publish your research
Open access publishing
Products and services
Our products
Librarians
Societies
Partners and advertisers
Our imprints
Springer
Nature Portfolio
BMC
Palgrave Macmillan
Apress
Your privacy choices/Manage cookies
Your US state privacy rights
Accessibility statement
Terms and conditions
Privacy policy
Help and support
49.157.13.121
Not affiliated
© 2024 Springer Nature
Feminist Perspectives on Sex and Gender (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
Feminist Perspectives on Sex and Gender (Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy)
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy
Menu
Browse
Table of Contents
What's New
Random Entry
Chronological
Archives
About
Editorial Information
About the SEP
Editorial Board
How to Cite the SEP
Special Characters
Advanced Tools
Contact
Support SEP
Support the SEP
PDFs for SEP Friends
Make a Donation
SEPIA for Libraries
Entry Navigation
Entry Contents
Bibliography
Academic Tools
Friends PDF Preview
Author and Citation Info
Back to Top
Feminist Perspectives on Sex and GenderFirst published Mon May 12, 2008; substantive revision Tue Jan 18, 2022
Feminism is said to be the movement to end women’s oppression
(hooks 2000, 26). One possible way to understand ‘woman’
in this claim is to take it as a sex term: ‘woman’ picks
out human females and being a human female depends on various
biological and anatomical features (like genitalia). Historically many
feminists have understood ‘woman’ differently: not as a
sex term, but as a gender term that depends on social and cultural
factors (like social position). In so doing, they distinguished sex
(being female or male) from gender (being a woman or a man), although
most ordinary language users appear to treat the two interchangeably.
In feminist philosophy, this distinction has generated a lively
debate. Central questions include: What does it mean for gender to be
distinct from sex, if anything at all? How should we understand the
claim that gender depends on social and/or cultural factors? What does
it mean to be gendered woman, man, or genderqueer? This entry outlines
and discusses distinctly feminist debates on sex and gender
considering both historical and more contemporary positions.
1. The sex/gender distinction.
1.1 Biological determinism
1.2 Gender terminology
2. Gender as socially constructed
2.1 Gender socialisation
2.2 Gender as feminine and masculine personality
2.3 Gender as feminine and masculine sexuality
3. Problems with the sex/gender distinction
3.1 Is gender uniform?
3.1.1 Particularity argument
3.1.2 Normativity argument
3.2 Is sex classification solely a matter of biology?
3.3 Are sex and gender distinct?
3.4 Is the sex/gender distinction useful?
4. Women as a group
4.1 Gender nominalism
4.1.1 Gendered social series
4.1.2 Resemblance nominalism
4.2 Neo gender realism
4.2.1 Social subordination and gender
4.2.2 Gender uniessentialism
4.2.3 Gender as positionality
5. Beyond the Binary
6. Conclusion
Bibliography
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources
Related Entries
1. The sex/gender distinction.
The terms ‘sex’ and ‘gender’ mean different
things to different feminist theorists and neither are easy or
straightforward to characterise. Sketching out some feminist history
of the terms provides a helpful starting point.
1.1 Biological determinism
Most people ordinarily seem to think that sex and gender are
coextensive: women are human females, men are human males. Many
feminists have historically disagreed and have endorsed the sex/
gender distinction. Provisionally: ‘sex’ denotes human
females and males depending on biological features
(chromosomes, sex organs, hormones and other physical features);
‘gender’ denotes women and men depending on
social factors (social role, position, behaviour or
identity). The main feminist motivation for making this distinction
was to counter biological determinism or the view that biology is
destiny.
A typical example of a biological determinist view is that of Geddes
and Thompson who, in 1889, argued that social, psychological and
behavioural traits were caused by metabolic state. Women supposedly
conserve energy (being ‘anabolic’) and this makes them
passive, conservative, sluggish, stable and uninterested in politics.
Men expend their surplus energy (being ‘katabolic’) and
this makes them eager, energetic, passionate, variable and, thereby,
interested in political and social matters. These biological
‘facts’ about metabolic states were used not only to
explain behavioural differences between women and men but also to
justify what our social and political arrangements ought to be. More
specifically, they were used to argue for withholding from women
political rights accorded to men because (according to Geddes and
Thompson) “what was decided among the prehistoric Protozoa
cannot be annulled by Act of Parliament” (quoted from Moi 1999,
18). It would be inappropriate to grant women political rights, as
they are simply not suited to have those rights; it would also be
futile since women (due to their biology) would simply not be
interested in exercising their political rights. To counter this kind
of biological determinism, feminists have argued that behavioural and
psychological differences have social, rather than biological, causes.
For instance, Simone de Beauvoir famously claimed that one is not
born, but rather becomes a woman, and that “social
discrimination produces in women moral and intellectual effects so
profound that they appear to be caused by nature” (Beauvoir 1972
[original 1949], 18; for more, see the entry on
Simone de Beauvoir).
Commonly observed behavioural traits associated with women and men,
then, are not caused by anatomy or chromosomes. Rather, they are
culturally learned or acquired.
Although biological determinism of the kind endorsed by Geddes and
Thompson is nowadays uncommon, the idea that behavioural and
psychological differences between women and men have biological causes
has not disappeared. In the 1970s, sex differences were used to argue
that women should not become airline pilots since they will be
hormonally unstable once a month and, therefore, unable to perform
their duties as well as men (Rogers 1999, 11). More recently,
differences in male and female brains have been said to explain
behavioural differences; in particular, the anatomy of corpus
callosum, a bundle of nerves that connects the right and left cerebral
hemispheres, is thought to be responsible for various psychological
and behavioural differences. For instance, in 1992, a Time
magazine article surveyed then prominent biological explanations of
differences between women and men claiming that women’s thicker
corpus callosums could explain what ‘women’s
intuition’ is based on and impair women’s ability to
perform some specialised visual-spatial skills, like reading maps
(Gorman 1992). Anne Fausto-Sterling has questioned the idea that
differences in corpus callosums cause behavioural and psychological
differences. First, the corpus callosum is a highly variable piece of
anatomy; as a result, generalisations about its size, shape and
thickness that hold for women and men in general should be viewed with
caution. Second, differences in adult human corpus callosums are not
found in infants; this may suggest that physical brain differences
actually develop as responses to differential treatment. Third, given
that visual-spatial skills (like map reading) can be improved by
practice, even if women and men’s corpus callosums differ, this
does not make the resulting behavioural differences immutable.
(Fausto-Sterling 2000b, chapter 5).
1.2 Gender terminology
In order to distinguish biological differences from
social/psychological ones and to talk about the latter, feminists
appropriated the term ‘gender’. Psychologists writing on
transsexuality were the first to employ gender terminology in this
sense. Until the 1960s, ‘gender’ was often used to refer
to masculine and feminine words, like le and la in
French. However, in order to explain why some people felt that they
were ‘trapped in the wrong bodies’, the psychologist
Robert Stoller (1968) began using the terms ‘sex’ to pick
out biological traits and ‘gender’ to pick out the amount
of femininity and masculinity a person exhibited. Although (by and
large) a person’s sex and gender complemented each other,
separating out these terms seemed to make theoretical sense allowing
Stoller to explain the phenomenon of transsexuality:
transsexuals’ sex and gender simply don’t match.
Along with psychologists like Stoller, feminists found it useful to
distinguish sex and gender. This enabled them to argue that many
differences between women and men were socially produced and,
therefore, changeable. Gayle Rubin (for instance) uses the phrase
‘sex/gender system’ in order to describe “a set of
arrangements by which the biological raw material of human sex and
procreation is shaped by human, social intervention” (1975,
165). Rubin employed this system to articulate that “part of
social life which is the locus of the oppression of women”
(1975, 159) describing gender as the “socially imposed division
of the sexes” (1975, 179). Rubin’s thought was that
although biological differences are fixed, gender differences are the
oppressive results of social interventions that dictate how women and
men should behave. Women are oppressed as women and “by
having to be women” (Rubin 1975, 204). However, since
gender is social, it is thought to be mutable and alterable by
political and social reform that would ultimately bring an end to
women’s subordination. Feminism should aim to create a
“genderless (though not sexless) society, in which one’s
sexual anatomy is irrelevant to who one is, what one does, and with
whom one makes love” (Rubin 1975, 204).
In some earlier interpretations, like Rubin’s, sex and gender
were thought to complement one another. The slogan ‘Gender is
the social interpretation of sex’ captures this view. Nicholson
calls this ‘the coat-rack view’ of gender: our sexed
bodies are like coat racks and “provide the site upon which
gender [is] constructed” (1994, 81). Gender conceived of as
masculinity and femininity is superimposed upon the
‘coat-rack’ of sex as each society imposes on sexed bodies
their cultural conceptions of how males and females should behave.
This socially constructs gender differences – or the amount of
femininity/masculinity of a person – upon our sexed bodies. That
is, according to this interpretation, all humans are either male or
female; their sex is fixed. But cultures interpret sexed bodies
differently and project different norms on those bodies thereby
creating feminine and masculine persons. Distinguishing sex and
gender, however, also enables the two to come apart: they are
separable in that one can be sexed male and yet be gendered a woman,
or vice versa (Haslanger 2000b; Stoljar 1995).
So, this group of feminist arguments against biological determinism
suggested that gender differences result from cultural practices and
social expectations. Nowadays it is more common to denote this by
saying that gender is socially constructed. This means that genders
(women and men) and gendered traits (like being nurturing or
ambitious) are the “intended or unintended product[s] of a
social practice” (Haslanger 1995, 97). But which social
practices construct gender, what social construction is and what being
of a certain gender amounts to are major feminist controversies. There
is no consensus on these issues. (See the entry on
intersections between analytic and continental feminism
for more on different ways to understand gender.)
2. Gender as socially constructed
2.1 Gender socialisation
One way to interpret Beauvoir’s claim that one is not born but
rather becomes a woman is to take it as a claim about gender
socialisation: females become women through a process whereby they
acquire feminine traits and learn feminine behaviour. Masculinity and
femininity are thought to be products of nurture or how individuals
are brought up. They are causally constructed (Haslanger
1995, 98): social forces either have a causal role in bringing
gendered individuals into existence or (to some substantial sense)
shape the way we are qua women and men. And the mechanism of
construction is social learning. For instance, Kate Millett takes
gender differences to have “essentially cultural, rather than
biological bases” that result from differential treatment (1971,
28–9). For her, gender is “the sum total of the
parents’, the peers’, and the culture’s notions of
what is appropriate to each gender by way of temperament, character,
interests, status, worth, gesture, and expression” (Millett
1971, 31). Feminine and masculine gender-norms, however, are
problematic in that gendered behaviour conveniently fits with and
reinforces women’s subordination so that women are socialised
into subordinate social roles: they learn to be passive, ignorant,
docile, emotional helpmeets for men (Millett 1971, 26). However, since
these roles are simply learned, we can create more equal societies by
‘unlearning’ social roles. That is, feminists should aim
to diminish the influence of socialisation.
Social learning theorists hold that a huge array of different
influences socialise us as women and men. This being the case, it is
extremely difficult to counter gender socialisation. For instance,
parents often unconsciously treat their female and male children
differently. When parents have been asked to describe their
24-hour old infants, they have done so using
gender-stereotypic language: boys are describes as strong, alert and
coordinated and girls as tiny, soft and delicate. Parents’
treatment of their infants further reflects these descriptions whether
they are aware of this or not (Renzetti & Curran 1992, 32). Some
socialisation is more overt: children are often dressed in gender
stereotypical clothes and colours (boys are dressed in blue, girls in
pink) and parents tend to buy their children gender stereotypical
toys. They also (intentionally or not) tend to reinforce certain
‘appropriate’ behaviours. While the precise form of gender
socialization has changed since the onset of second-wave feminism,
even today girls are discouraged from playing sports like football or
from playing ‘rough and tumble’ games and are more likely
than boys to be given dolls or cooking toys to play with; boys are
told not to ‘cry like a baby’ and are more likely to be
given masculine toys like trucks and guns (for more, see Kimmel 2000,
122–126).[1]
According to social learning theorists, children are also influenced
by what they observe in the world around them. This, again, makes
countering gender socialisation difficult. For one, children’s
books have portrayed males and females in blatantly stereotypical
ways: for instance, males as adventurers and leaders, and females as
helpers and followers. One way to address gender stereotyping in
children’s books has been to portray females in independent
roles and males as non-aggressive and nurturing (Renzetti & Curran
1992, 35). Some publishers have attempted an alternative approach by
making their characters, for instance, gender-neutral animals or
genderless imaginary creatures (like TV’s Teletubbies). However,
parents reading books with gender-neutral or genderless characters
often undermine the publishers’ efforts by reading them to their
children in ways that depict the characters as either feminine or
masculine. According to Renzetti and Curran, parents labelled the
overwhelming majority of gender-neutral characters masculine whereas
those characters that fit feminine gender stereotypes (for instance,
by being helpful and caring) were labelled feminine (1992, 35).
Socialising influences like these are still thought to send implicit
messages regarding how females and males should act and are expected
to act shaping us into feminine and masculine persons.
2.2 Gender as feminine and masculine personality
Nancy Chodorow (1978; 1995) has criticised social learning theory as
too simplistic to explain gender differences (see also Deaux &
Major 1990; Gatens 1996). Instead, she holds that gender is a matter
of having feminine and masculine personalities that develop in early
infancy as responses to prevalent parenting practices. In particular,
gendered personalities develop because women tend to be the primary
caretakers of small children. Chodorow holds that because mothers (or
other prominent females) tend to care for infants, infant male and
female psychic development differs. Crudely put: the mother-daughter
relationship differs from the mother-son relationship because mothers
are more likely to identify with their daughters than their sons. This
unconsciously prompts the mother to encourage her son to
psychologically individuate himself from her thereby prompting him to
develop well defined and rigid ego boundaries. However, the mother
unconsciously discourages the daughter from individuating herself
thereby prompting the daughter to develop flexible and blurry ego
boundaries. Childhood gender socialisation further builds on and
reinforces these unconsciously developed ego boundaries finally
producing feminine and masculine persons (1995, 202–206). This
perspective has its roots in Freudian psychoanalytic theory, although
Chodorow’s approach differs in many ways from Freud’s.
Gendered personalities are supposedly manifested in common gender
stereotypical behaviour. Take emotional dependency. Women are
stereotypically more emotional and emotionally dependent upon others
around them, supposedly finding it difficult to distinguish their own
interests and wellbeing from the interests and wellbeing of their
children and partners. This is said to be because of their blurry and
(somewhat) confused ego boundaries: women find it hard to distinguish
their own needs from the needs of those around them because they
cannot sufficiently individuate themselves from those close to them.
By contrast, men are stereotypically emotionally detached, preferring
a career where dispassionate and distanced thinking are virtues. These
traits are said to result from men’s well-defined ego boundaries
that enable them to prioritise their own needs and interests sometimes
at the expense of others’ needs and interests.
Chodorow thinks that these gender differences should and can be
changed. Feminine and masculine personalities play a crucial role in
women’s oppression since they make females overly attentive to
the needs of others and males emotionally deficient. In order to
correct the situation, both male and female parents should be equally
involved in parenting (Chodorow 1995, 214). This would help in
ensuring that children develop sufficiently individuated senses of
selves without becoming overly detached, which in turn helps to
eradicate common gender stereotypical behaviours.
2.3 Gender as feminine and masculine sexuality
Catharine MacKinnon develops her theory of gender as a theory of
sexuality. Very roughly: the social meaning of sex (gender) is created
by sexual objectification of women whereby women are viewed and
treated as objects for satisfying men’s desires
(MacKinnon 1989). Masculinity is defined as sexual dominance,
femininity as sexual submissiveness: genders are “created
through the eroticization of dominance and submission. The man/woman
difference and the dominance/submission dynamic define each other.
This is the social meaning of sex” (MacKinnon 1989, 113). For
MacKinnon, gender is constitutively constructed: in defining
genders (or masculinity and femininity) we must make reference to
social factors (see Haslanger 1995, 98). In particular, we must make
reference to the position one occupies in the sexualised
dominance/submission dynamic: men occupy the sexually dominant
position, women the sexually submissive one. As a result, genders are
by definition hierarchical and this hierarchy is
fundamentally tied to sexualised power relations. The notion of
‘gender equality’, then, does not make sense to MacKinnon.
If sexuality ceased to be a manifestation of dominance, hierarchical
genders (that are defined in terms of sexuality) would cease
to exist.
So, gender difference for MacKinnon is not a matter of having a
particular psychological orientation or behavioural pattern; rather,
it is a function of sexuality that is hierarchal in patriarchal
societies. This is not to say that men are naturally disposed
to sexually objectify women or that women are naturally
submissive. Instead, male and female sexualities are socially
conditioned: men have been conditioned to find women’s
subordination sexy and women have been conditioned to find a
particular male version of female sexuality as erotic – one in
which it is erotic to be sexually submissive. For MacKinnon, both
female and male sexual desires are defined from a male point of view
that is conditioned by pornography (MacKinnon 1989, chapter 7).
Bluntly put: pornography portrays a false picture of ‘what women
want’ suggesting that women in actual fact are and want to be
submissive. This conditions men’s sexuality so that they view
women’s submission as sexy. And male dominance enforces this
male version of sexuality onto women, sometimes by force.
MacKinnon’s thought is not that male dominance is a result of
social learning (see 2.1.); rather, socialization is an expression of
power. That is, socialized differences in masculine and feminine
traits, behaviour, and roles are not responsible for power
inequalities. Females and males (roughly put) are socialised
differently because there are underlying power inequalities. As
MacKinnon puts it, ‘dominance’ (power relations) is prior
to ‘difference’ (traits, behaviour and roles) (see,
MacKinnon 1989, chapter 12). MacKinnon, then, sees legal restrictions
on pornography as paramount to ending women’s subordinate status
that stems from their gender.
3. Problems with the sex/gender distinction
3.1 Is gender uniform?
The positions outlined above share an underlying metaphysical
perspective on gender: gender
realism.[2]
That is, women as a group are assumed to share some characteristic
feature, experience, common condition or criterion that defines their
gender and the possession of which makes some individuals women (as
opposed to, say, men). All women are thought to differ from
all men in this respect (or respects). For example, MacKinnon
thought that being treated in sexually objectifying ways is the common
condition that defines women’s gender and what women as
women share. All women differ from all men in this respect.
Further, pointing out females who are not sexually objectified does
not provide a counterexample to MacKinnon’s view. Being sexually
objectified is constitutive of being a woman; a female who
escapes sexual objectification, then, would not count as a woman.
One may want to critique the three accounts outlined by rejecting the
particular details of each account. (For instance, see Spelman [1988,
chapter 4] for a critique of the details of Chodorow’s view.) A
more thoroughgoing critique has been levelled at the general
metaphysical perspective of gender realism that underlies these
positions. It has come under sustained attack on two grounds: first,
that it fails to take into account racial, cultural and class
differences between women (particularity argument); second, that it
posits a normative ideal of womanhood (normativity argument).
3.1.1 Particularity argument
Elizabeth Spelman (1988) has influentially argued against gender
realism with her particularity argument. Roughly: gender realists
mistakenly assume that gender is constructed independently of race,
class, ethnicity and nationality. If gender were separable from, for
example, race and class in this manner, all women would experience
womanhood in the same way. And this is clearly false. For instance,
Harris (1993) and Stone (2007) criticise MacKinnon’s view, that
sexual objectification is the common condition that defines
women’s gender, for failing to take into account differences in
women’s backgrounds that shape their sexuality. The history of
racist oppression illustrates that during slavery black women were
‘hypersexualised’ and thought to be always sexually
available whereas white women were thought to be pure and sexually
virtuous. In fact, the rape of a black woman was thought to be
impossible (Harris 1993). So, (the argument goes) sexual
objectification cannot serve as the common condition for womanhood
since it varies considerably depending on one’s race and
class.[3]
For Spelman, the perspective of ‘white solipsism’
underlies gender realists’ mistake. They assumed that all women
share some “golden nugget of womanness” (Spelman 1988,
159) and that the features constitutive of such a nugget are the same
for all women regardless of their particular cultural backgrounds.
Next, white Western middle-class feminists accounted for the shared
features simply by reflecting on the cultural features that condition
their gender as women thus supposing that “the
womanness underneath the Black woman’s skin is a white
woman’s, and deep down inside the Latina woman is an Anglo woman
waiting to burst through an obscuring cultural shroud” (Spelman
1988, 13). In so doing, Spelman claims, white middle-class Western
feminists passed off their particular view of gender as “a
metaphysical truth” (1988, 180) thereby privileging some women
while marginalising others. In failing to see the importance of race
and class in gender construction, white middle-class Western feminists
conflated “the condition of one group of women with the
condition of all” (Spelman 1988, 3).
Betty Friedan’s (1963) well-known work is a case in point of
white
solipsism.[4]
Friedan saw domesticity as the main vehicle of gender oppression and
called upon women in general to find jobs outside the home. But she
failed to realize that women from less privileged backgrounds, often
poor and non-white, already worked outside the home to support their
families. Friedan’s suggestion, then, was applicable only to a
particular sub-group of women (white middle-class Western housewives).
But it was mistakenly taken to apply to all women’s lives
— a mistake that was generated by Friedan’s failure to
take women’s racial and class differences into account (hooks
2000, 1–3).
Spelman further holds that since social conditioning creates
femininity and societies (and sub-groups) that condition it differ
from one another, femininity must be differently conditioned in
different societies. For her, “females become not simply women
but particular kinds of women” (Spelman 1988, 113): white
working-class women, black middle-class women, poor Jewish women,
wealthy aristocratic European women, and so on.
This line of thought has been extremely influential in feminist
philosophy. For instance, Young holds that Spelman has
definitively shown that gender realism is untenable (1997,
13). Mikkola (2006) argues that this isn’t so. The arguments
Spelman makes do not undermine the idea that there is some
characteristic feature, experience, common condition or criterion that
defines women’s gender; they simply point out that some
particular ways of cashing out what defines womanhood are misguided.
So, although Spelman is right to reject those accounts that falsely
take the feature that conditions white middle-class Western
feminists’ gender to condition women’s gender in general,
this leaves open the possibility that women qua women do
share something that defines their gender. (See also Haslanger [2000a]
for a discussion of why gender realism is not necessarily untenable,
and Stoljar [2011] for a discussion of Mikkola’s critique of
Spelman.)
3.1.2 Normativity argument
Judith Butler critiques the sex/gender distinction on two grounds.
They critique gender realism with their normativity argument (1999
[original 1990], chapter 1); they also hold that the sex/gender
distinction is unintelligible (this will be discussed in section
3.3.). Butler’s normativity argument is not straightforwardly
directed at the metaphysical perspective of gender realism, but rather
at its political counterpart: identity politics. This is a
form of political mobilization based on membership in some group (e.g.
racial, ethnic, cultural, gender) and group membership is thought to
be delimited by some common experiences, conditions or features that
define the group (Heyes 2000, 58; see also the entry on
Identity Politics).
Feminist identity politics, then, presupposes gender realism in that
feminist politics is said to be mobilized around women as a group (or
category) where membership in this group is fixed by some condition,
experience or feature that women supposedly share and that defines
their gender.
Butler’s normativity argument makes two claims. The first is
akin to Spelman’s particularity argument: unitary gender notions
fail to take differences amongst women into account thus failing to
recognise “the multiplicity of cultural, social, and political
intersections in which the concrete array of ‘women’ are
constructed” (Butler 1999, 19–20). In their attempt to
undercut biologically deterministic ways of defining what it means to
be a woman, feminists inadvertently created new socially constructed
accounts of supposedly shared femininity. Butler’s second claim
is that such false gender realist accounts are normative. That is, in
their attempt to fix feminism’s subject matter, feminists
unwittingly defined the term ‘woman’ in a way that implies
there is some correct way to be gendered a woman (Butler 1999, 5).
That the definition of the term ‘woman’ is fixed
supposedly “operates as a policing force which generates and
legitimizes certain practices, experiences, etc., and curtails and
delegitimizes others” (Nicholson 1998, 293). Following this line
of thought, one could say that, for instance, Chodorow’s view of
gender suggests that ‘real’ women have feminine
personalities and that these are the women feminism should be
concerned about. If one does not exhibit a distinctly feminine
personality, the implication is that one is not ‘really’ a
member of women’s category nor does one properly qualify for
feminist political representation.
Butler’s second claim is based on their view
that“[i]dentity categories [like that of women] are never merely
descriptive, but always normative, and as such, exclusionary”
(Butler 1991, 160). That is, the mistake of those feminists Butler
critiques was not that they provided the incorrect definition of
‘woman’. Rather, (the argument goes) their mistake was to
attempt to define the term ‘woman’ at all. Butler’s
view is that ‘woman’ can never be defined in a way that
does not prescribe some “unspoken normative requirements”
(like having a feminine personality) that women should conform to
(Butler 1999, 9). Butler takes this to be a feature of terms like
‘woman’ that purport to pick out (what they call)
‘identity categories’. They seem to assume that
‘woman’ can never be used in a non-ideological way (Moi
1999, 43) and that it will always encode conditions that are not
satisfied by everyone we think of as women. Some explanation for this
comes from Butler’s view that all processes of drawing
categorical distinctions involve evaluative and normative commitments;
these in turn involve the exercise of power and reflect the conditions
of those who are socially powerful (Witt 1995).
In order to better understand Butler’s critique, consider their
account of gender performativity. For them, standard feminist accounts
take gendered individuals to have some essential properties
qua gendered individuals or a gender core by virtue of which
one is either a man or a woman. This view assumes that women and men,
qua women and men, are bearers of various essential and
accidental attributes where the former secure gendered persons’
persistence through time as so gendered. But according to Butler this
view is false: (i) there are no such essential properties, and (ii)
gender is an illusion maintained by prevalent power structures. First,
feminists are said to think that genders are socially constructed in
that they have the following essential attributes (Butler 1999, 24):
women are females with feminine behavioural traits, being
heterosexuals whose desire is directed at men; men are males with
masculine behavioural traits, being heterosexuals whose desire is
directed at women. These are the attributes necessary for gendered
individuals and those that enable women and men to persist through
time as women and men. Individuals have “intelligible
genders” (Butler 1999, 23) if they exhibit this sequence of
traits in a coherent manner (where sexual desire follows from sexual
orientation that in turn follows from feminine/ masculine behaviours
thought to follow from biological sex). Social forces in general deem
individuals who exhibit incoherent gender sequences (like
lesbians) to be doing their gender ‘wrong’ and they
actively discourage such sequencing of traits, for instance, via
name-calling and overt homophobic discrimination. Think back to what
was said above: having a certain conception of what women are like
that mirrors the conditions of socially powerful (white, middle-class,
heterosexual, Western) women functions to marginalize and police those
who do not fit this conception.
These gender cores, supposedly encoding the above traits, however, are
nothing more than illusions created by ideals and practices that seek
to render gender uniform through heterosexism, the view that
heterosexuality is natural and homosexuality is deviant (Butler 1999,
42). Gender cores are constructed as if they somehow
naturally belong to women and men thereby creating gender dimorphism
or the belief that one must be either a masculine male or a feminine
female. But gender dimorphism only serves a heterosexist social order
by implying that since women and men are sharply opposed, it is
natural to sexually desire the opposite sex or gender.
Further, being feminine and desiring men (for instance) are standardly
assumed to be expressions of one’s gender as a woman. Butler
denies this and holds that gender is really performative. It is not
“a stable identity or locus of agency from which various acts
follow; rather, gender is … instituted … through a
stylized repetition of [habitual] acts”
(Butler 1999, 179): through wearing certain gender-coded clothing,
walking and sitting in certain gender-coded ways, styling one’s
hair in gender-coded manner and so on. Gender is not something one is,
it is something one does; it is a sequence of acts, a doing rather
than a being. And repeatedly engaging in ‘feminising’ and
‘masculinising’ acts congeals gender thereby making people
falsely think of gender as something they naturally are.
Gender only comes into being through these gendering acts: a female
who has sex with men does not express her gender as a woman.
This activity (amongst others) makes her gendered a
woman.
The constitutive acts that gender individuals create genders as
“compelling illusion[s]” (Butler 1990, 271). Our gendered
classification scheme is a strong pragmatic construction:
social factors wholly determine our use of the scheme and the scheme
fails to represent accurately any ‘facts of the matter’
(Haslanger 1995, 100). People think that there are true and real
genders, and those deemed to be doing their gender ‘wrong’
are not socially sanctioned. But, genders are true and real only to
the extent that they are performed (Butler 1990, 278–9). It does
not make sense, then, to say of a male-to-female trans person that
s/he is really a man who only appears to be a woman.
Instead, males dressing up and acting in ways that are associated with
femininity “show that [as Butler suggests] ‘being’
feminine is just a matter of doing certain activities” (Stone
2007, 64). As a result, the trans person’s gender is just as
real or true as anyone else’s who is a
‘traditionally’ feminine female or masculine male (Butler
1990,
278).[5]
Without heterosexism that compels people to engage in certain
gendering acts, there would not be any genders at all. And ultimately
the aim should be to abolish norms that compel people to act in these
gendering ways.
For Butler, given that gender is performative, the appropriate
response to feminist identity politics involves two things. First,
feminists should understand ‘woman’ as open-ended and
“a term in process, a becoming, a constructing that cannot
rightfully be said to originate or end … it is open to
intervention and resignification” (Butler 1999, 43). That is,
feminists should not try to define ‘woman’ at all. Second,
the category of women “ought not to be the foundation of
feminist politics” (Butler 1999, 9). Rather, feminists should
focus on providing an account of how power functions and shapes our
understandings of womanhood not only in the society at large but also
within the feminist movement.
3.2 Is sex classification solely a matter of biology?
Many people, including many feminists, have ordinarily taken sex
ascriptions to be solely a matter of biology with no social or
cultural dimension. It is commonplace to think that there are only two
sexes and that biological sex classifications are utterly
unproblematic. By contrast, some feminists have argued that sex
classifications are not unproblematic and that they are not solely a
matter of biology. In order to make sense of this, it is helpful to
distinguish object- and idea-construction (see Haslanger 2003b for
more): social forces can be said to construct certain kinds of objects
(e.g. sexed bodies or gendered individuals) and certain kinds of ideas
(e.g. sex or gender concepts). First, take the object-construction of
sexed bodies. Secondary sex characteristics, or the physiological and
biological features commonly associated with males and females, are
affected by social practices. In some societies, females’ lower
social status has meant that they have been fed less and so, the lack
of nutrition has had the effect of making them smaller in size (Jaggar
1983, 37). Uniformity in muscular shape, size and strength within sex
categories is not caused entirely by biological factors, but depends
heavily on exercise opportunities: if males and females were allowed
the same exercise opportunities and equal encouragement to exercise,
it is thought that bodily dimorphism would diminish (Fausto-Sterling
1993a, 218). A number of medical phenomena involving bones (like
osteoporosis) have social causes directly related to expectations
about gender, women’s diet and their exercise opportunities
(Fausto-Sterling 2005). These examples suggest that physiological
features thought to be sex-specific traits not affected by social and
cultural factors are, after all, to some extent products of social
conditioning. Social conditioning, then, shapes our biology.
Second, take the idea-construction of sex concepts. Our concept of
sex is said to be a product of social forces in the sense
that what counts as sex is shaped by social meanings. Standardly,
those with XX-chromosomes, ovaries that produce large egg cells,
female genitalia, a relatively high proportion of ‘female’
hormones, and other secondary sex characteristics (relatively small
body size, less body hair) count as biologically female. Those with
XY-chromosomes, testes that produce small sperm cells, male genitalia,
a relatively high proportion of ‘male’ hormones and other
secondary sex traits (relatively large body size, significant amounts
of body hair) count as male. This understanding is fairly recent. The
prevalent scientific view from Ancient Greeks until the late
18th century, did not consider female and male sexes to be
distinct categories with specific traits; instead, a ‘one-sex
model’ held that males and females were members of the same sex
category. Females’ genitals were thought to be the same as
males’ but simply directed inside the body; ovaries and testes
(for instance) were referred to by the same term and whether the term
referred to the former or the latter was made clear by the context
(Laqueur 1990, 4). It was not until the late 1700s that scientists
began to think of female and male anatomies as radically different
moving away from the ‘one-sex model’ of a single sex
spectrum to the (nowadays prevalent) ‘two-sex model’ of
sexual dimorphism. (For an alternative view, see King 2013.)
Fausto-Sterling has argued that this ‘two-sex model’
isn’t straightforward either (1993b; 2000a; 2000b). Based on a
meta-study of empirical medical research, she estimates that 1.7% of
population fail to neatly fall within the usual sex classifications
possessing various combinations of different sex characteristics
(Fausto-Sterling 2000a, 20). In her earlier work, she claimed that
intersex individuals make up (at least) three further sex classes:
‘herms’ who possess one testis and one ovary;
‘merms’ who possess testes, some aspects of female
genitalia but no ovaries; and ‘ferms’ who have ovaries,
some aspects of male genitalia but no testes (Fausto-Sterling 1993b,
21). (In her [2000a], Fausto-Sterling notes that these labels were put
forward tongue–in–cheek.) Recognition of intersex people
suggests that feminists (and society at large) are wrong to think that
humans are either female or male.
To illustrate further the idea-construction of sex, consider the case
of the athlete Maria Patiño. Patiño has female
genitalia, has always considered herself to be female and was
considered so by others. However, she was discovered to have XY
chromosomes and was barred from competing in women’s sports
(Fausto-Sterling 2000b, 1–3). Patiño’s genitalia
were at odds with her chromosomes and the latter were taken to
determine her sex. Patiño successfully fought to be recognised
as a female athlete arguing that her chromosomes alone were not
sufficient to not make her female. Intersex people, like
Patiño, illustrate that our understandings of sex differ and
suggest that there is no immediately obvious way to settle what sex
amounts to purely biologically or scientifically. Deciding what sex is
involves evaluative judgements that are influenced by social
factors.
Insofar as our cultural conceptions affect our understandings of sex,
feminists must be much more careful about sex classifications and
rethink what sex amounts to (Stone 2007, chapter 1). More
specifically, intersex people illustrate that sex traits associated
with females and males need not always go together and that
individuals can have some mixture of these traits. This suggests to
Stone that sex is a cluster concept: it is sufficient to
satisfy enough of the sex features that tend to cluster together in
order to count as being of a particular sex. But, one need not satisfy
all of those features or some arbitrarily chosen supposedly
necessary sex feature, like chromosomes (Stone 2007, 44).
This makes sex a matter of degree and sex classifications should take
place on a spectrum: one can be more or less female/male but there is
no sharp distinction between the two. Further, intersex people (along
with trans people) are located at the centre of the sex spectrum and
in many cases their sex will be indeterminate (Stone 2007).
More recently, Ayala and Vasilyeva (2015) have argued for an inclusive
and extended conception of sex: just as certain tools can be seen to
extend our minds beyond the limits of our brains (e.g. white canes),
other tools (like dildos) can extend our sex beyond our bodily
boundaries. This view aims to motivate the idea that what counts as
sex should not be determined by looking inwards at genitalia or other
anatomical features. In a different vein, Ásta (2018) argues
that sex is a conferred social property. This follows her more general
conferralist framework to analyse all social properties: properties
that are conferred by others thereby generating a social status that
consists in contextually specific constraints and enablements on
individual behaviour. The general schema for conferred properties is
as follows (Ásta 2018, 8):
Conferred property: what property is conferred.
Who: who the subjects are.
What: what attitude, state, or action of the subjects
matter.
When: under what conditions the conferral takes
place.
Base property: what the subjects are attempting to
track (consciously or not), if anything.
With being of a certain sex (e.g. male, female) in mind, Ásta
holds that it is a conferred property that merely aims to track
physical features. Hence sex is a social – or in fact, an
institutional – property rather than a natural one. The schema
for sex goes as follows (72):
Conferred property: being female, male.
Who: legal authorities, drawing on the expert opinion
of doctors, other medical personnel.
What: “the recording of a sex in official
documents ... The judgment of the doctors (and others) as to what sex
role might be the most fitting, given the biological characteristics
present.”
When: at birth or after surgery/ hormonal
treatment.
Base property: “the aim is to track as many
sex-stereotypical characteristics as possible, and doctors perform
surgery in cases where that might help bring the physical
characteristics more in line with the stereotype of male and
female.”
This (among other things) offers a debunking analysis of sex: it may
appear to be a natural property, but on the conferralist analysis is
better understood as a conferred legal status. Ásta holds that
gender too is a conferred property, but contra the discussion in the
following section, she does not think that this collapses the
distinction between sex and gender: sex and gender are differently
conferred albeit both satisfying the general schema noted above.
Nonetheless, on the conferralist framework what underlies both sex and
gender is the idea of social construction as social significance:
sex-stereotypical characteristics are taken to be socially significant
context specifically, whereby they become the basis for conferring sex
onto individuals and this brings with it various constraints and
enablements on individuals and their behaviour. This fits object- and
idea-constructions introduced above, although offers a different
general framework to analyse the matter at hand.
3.3 Are sex and gender distinct?
In addition to arguing against identity politics and for gender
performativity, Butler holds that distinguishing biological
sex from social gender is unintelligible. For them, both are
socially constructed:
If the immutable character of sex is contested, perhaps this construct
called ‘sex’ is as culturally constructed as gender;
indeed, perhaps it was always already gender, with the consequence
that the distinction between sex and gender turns out to be no
distinction at all. (Butler 1999, 10–11)
(Butler is not alone in claiming that there are no tenable
distinctions between nature/culture, biology/construction and
sex/gender. See also: Antony 1998; Gatens 1996; Grosz 1994; Prokhovnik
1999.) Butler makes two different claims in the passage cited: that
sex is a social construction, and that sex is gender. To unpack their
view, consider the two claims in turn. First, the idea that sex is a
social construct, for Butler, boils down to the view that our sexed
bodies are also performative and, so, they have “no ontological
status apart from the various acts which constitute [their]
reality” (1999, 173). Prima facie, this implausibly
implies that female and male bodies do not have independent existence
and that if gendering activities ceased, so would physical bodies.
This is not Butler’s claim; rather, their position is that
bodies viewed as the material foundations on which gender is
constructed, are themselves constructed as if they provide
such material foundations (Butler 1993). Cultural conceptions about
gender figure in “the very apparatus of production whereby sexes
themselves are established” (Butler 1999, 11).
For Butler, sexed bodies never exist outside social meanings and how
we understand gender shapes how we understand sex (1999, 139). Sexed
bodies are not empty matter on which gender is constructed and sex
categories are not picked out on the basis of objective features of
the world. Instead, our sexed bodies are themselves discursively
constructed: they are the way they are, at least to a substantial
extent, because of what is attributed to sexed bodies and how they are
classified (for discursive construction, see Haslanger 1995, 99). Sex
assignment (calling someone female or male) is normative (Butler 1993,
1).[6]
When the doctor calls a newly born infant a girl or a boy, s/he is
not making a descriptive claim, but a normative one. In fact, the
doctor is performing an illocutionary speech act (see the entry on
Speech Acts).
In effect, the doctor’s utterance makes infants into girls or
boys. We, then, engage in activities that make it seem as if sexes
naturally come in two and that being female or male is an objective
feature of the world, rather than being a consequence of certain
constitutive acts (that is, rather than being performative). And this
is what Butler means in saying that physical bodies never exist
outside cultural and social meanings, and that sex is as socially
constructed as gender. They do not deny that physical bodies exist.
But, they take our understanding of this existence to be a
product of social conditioning: social conditioning makes the
existence of physical bodies intelligible to us by discursively
constructing sexed bodies through certain constitutive acts. (For a
helpful introduction to Butler’s views, see Salih 2002.)
For Butler, sex assignment is always in some sense oppressive. Again,
this appears to be because of Butler’s general suspicion of
classification: sex classification can never be merely descriptive but
always has a normative element reflecting evaluative claims of those
who are powerful. Conducting a feminist genealogy of the body (or
examining why sexed bodies are thought to come naturally as female and
male), then, should ground feminist practice (Butler 1993,
28–9). Feminists should examine and uncover ways in which social
construction and certain acts that constitute sex shape our
understandings of sexed bodies, what kinds of meanings bodies acquire
and which practices and illocutionary speech acts ‘make’
our bodies into sexes. Doing so enables feminists to identity how
sexed bodies are socially constructed in order to resist such
construction.
However, given what was said above, it is far from obvious what we
should make of Butler’s claim that sex “was always already
gender” (1999, 11). Stone (2007) takes this to mean that sex
is gender but goes on to question it arguing that the social
construction of both sex and gender does not make sex identical to
gender. According to Stone, it would be more accurate for Butler to
say that claims about sex imply gender norms. That is, many
claims about sex traits (like ‘females are physically weaker
than males’) actually carry implications about how women and men
are expected to behave. To some extent the claim describes certain
facts. But, it also implies that females are not expected to do much
heavy lifting and that they would probably not be good at it. So,
claims about sex are not identical to claims about gender; rather,
they imply claims about gender norms (Stone 2007, 70).
3.4 Is the sex/gender distinction useful?
Some feminists hold that the sex/gender distinction is not useful. For
a start, it is thought to reflect politically problematic dualistic
thinking that undercuts feminist aims: the distinction is taken to
reflect and replicate androcentric oppositions between (for instance)
mind/body, culture/nature and reason/emotion that have been used to
justify women’s oppression (e.g. Grosz 1994; Prokhovnik 1999).
The thought is that in oppositions like these, one term is always
superior to the other and that the devalued term is usually associated
with women (Lloyd 1993). For instance, human subjectivity and agency
are identified with the mind but since women are usually identified
with their bodies, they are devalued as human subjects and agents. The
opposition between mind and body is said to further map on to other
distinctions, like reason/emotion, culture/nature,
rational/irrational, where one side of each distinction is devalued
(one’s bodily features are usually valued less that one’s
mind, rationality is usually valued more than irrationality) and women
are associated with the devalued terms: they are thought to be closer
to bodily features and nature than men, to be irrational, emotional
and so on. This is said to be evident (for instance) in job
interviews. Men are treated as gender-neutral persons and not asked
whether they are planning to take time off to have a family. By
contrast, that women face such queries illustrates that they are
associated more closely than men with bodily features to do with
procreation (Prokhovnik 1999, 126). The opposition between mind and
body, then, is thought to map onto the opposition between men and
women.
Now, the mind/body dualism is also said to map onto the sex/gender
distinction (Grosz 1994; Prokhovnik 1999). The idea is that gender
maps onto mind, sex onto body. Although not used by those endorsing
this view, the basic idea can be summed by the slogan ‘Gender is
between the ears, sex is between the legs’: the implication is
that, while sex is immutable, gender is something individuals have
control over – it is something we can alter and change through
individual choices. However, since women are said to be more closely
associated with biological features (and so, to map onto the body side
of the mind/body distinction) and men are treated as gender-neutral
persons (mapping onto the mind side), the implication is that
“man equals gender, which is associated with mind and choice,
freedom from body, autonomy, and with the public real; while woman
equals sex, associated with the body, reproduction,
‘natural’ rhythms and the private realm” (Prokhovnik
1999, 103). This is said to render the sex/gender distinction
inherently repressive and to drain it of any potential for
emancipation: rather than facilitating gender role choice for women,
it “actually functions to reinforce their association with body,
sex, and involuntary ‘natural’ rhythms” (Prokhovnik
1999, 103). Contrary to what feminists like Rubin argued, the
sex/gender distinction cannot be used as a theoretical tool that
dissociates conceptions of womanhood from biological and reproductive
features.
Moi has further argued that the sex/gender distinction is useless
given certain theoretical goals (1999, chapter 1). This is not to say
that it is utterly worthless; according to Moi, the sex/gender
distinction worked well to show that the historically prevalent
biological determinism was false. However, for her, the distinction
does no useful work “when it comes to producing a good theory of
subjectivity” (1999, 6) and “a concrete, historical
understanding of what it means to be a woman (or a man) in a given
society” (1999, 4–5). That is, the 1960s distinction
understood sex as fixed by biology without any cultural or historical
dimensions. This understanding, however, ignores lived experiences and
embodiment as aspects of womanhood (and manhood) by separating sex
from gender and insisting that womanhood is to do with the latter.
Rather, embodiment must be included in one’s theory that tries
to figure out what it is to be a woman (or a man).
Mikkola (2011) argues that the sex/gender distinction, which underlies
views like Rubin’s and MacKinnon’s, has certain
unintuitive and undesirable ontological commitments that render the
distinction politically unhelpful. First, claiming that gender is
socially constructed implies that the existence of women and men is a
mind-dependent matter. This suggests that we can do away with women
and men simply by altering some social practices, conventions or
conditions on which gender depends (whatever those are). However,
ordinary social agents find this unintuitive given that (ordinarily)
sex and gender are not distinguished. Second, claiming that gender is
a product of oppressive social forces suggests that doing away with
women and men should be feminism’s political goal. But this
harbours ontologically undesirable commitments since many ordinary
social agents view their gender to be a source of positive value. So,
feminism seems to want to do away with something that should not be
done away with, which is unlikely to motivate social agents to act in
ways that aim at gender justice. Given these problems, Mikkola argues
that feminists should give up the distinction on practical political
grounds.
Tomas Bogardus (2020) has argued in an even more radical sense against
the sex/gender distinction: as things stand, he holds, feminist
philosophers have merely assumed and asserted that the distinction
exists, instead of having offered good arguments for the distinction.
In other words, feminist philosophers allegedly have yet to offer good
reasons to think that ‘woman’ does not simply
pick out adult human females. Alex Byrne (2020) argues in a similar
vein: the term ‘woman’ does not pick out a social kind as
feminist philosophers have “assumed”. Instead,
“women are adult human females–nothing more, and nothing
less” (2020, 3801). Byrne offers six considerations to ground
this AHF (adult, human, female) conception.
It reproduces the dictionary definition of
‘woman’.
One would expect English to have a word that picks out the
category adult human female, and ‘woman’ is the only
candidate.
AHF explains how we sometimes know that an individual is a woman,
despite knowing nothing else relevant about her other than the fact
that she is an adult human female.
AHF stands or falls with the analogous thesis for girls, which can
be supported independently.
AHF predicts the correct verdict in cases of gender role
reversal.
AHF is supported by the fact that ‘woman’ and
‘female’ are often appropriately used as stylistic
variants of each other, even in
hyperintensional
contexts.
Robin Dembroff (2021) responds to Byrne and highlights various
problems with Byrne’s argument. First, framing: Byrne assumes
from the start that gender terms like ‘woman’ have a
single invariant meaning thereby failing to discuss the possibility of
terms like ‘woman’ having multiple meanings –
something that is a familiar claim made by feminist theorists from
various disciplines. Moreover, Byrne (according to Dembroff) assumes
without argument that there is a single, universal category of woman
– again, something that has been extensively discussed and
critiqued by feminist philosophers and theorists. Second,
Byrne’s conception of the ‘dominant’
meaning of woman is said to be cherry-picked and it ignores a
wealth of contexts outside of philosophy (like the media and the law)
where ‘woman’ has a meaning other than AHF.
Third, Byrne’s own distinction between biological and social
categories fails to establish what he intended to establish: namely,
that ‘woman’ picks out a biological rather than a social
kind. Hence, Dembroff holds, Byrne’s case fails by its own
lights. Byrne (2021) responds to Dembroff’s critique.
Others such as ‘gender critical feminists’ also hold views
about the sex/gender distinction in a spirit similar to Bogardus and
Byrne. For example, Holly Lawford-Smith (2021) takes the prevalent
sex/gender distinction, where ‘female’/‘male’
are used as sex terms and ‘woman’/’man’ as
gender terms, not to be helpful. Instead, she takes all of these to be
sex terms and holds that (the norms of) femininity/masculinity refer
to gender normativity. Because much of the gender critical
feminists’ discussion that philosophers have engaged in has
taken place in social media, public fora, and other sources outside
academic philosophy, this entry will not focus on these
discussions.
4. Women as a group
The various critiques of the sex/gender distinction have called into
question the viability of the category women. Feminism is the
movement to end the oppression women as a group face. But, how should
the category of women be understood if feminists accept the above
arguments that gender construction is not uniform, that a sharp
distinction between biological sex and social gender is false or (at
least) not useful, and that various features associated with women
play a role in what it is to be a woman, none of which are
individually necessary and jointly sufficient (like a variety of
social roles, positions, behaviours, traits, bodily features and
experiences)? Feminists must be able to address cultural and social
differences in gender construction if feminism is to be a genuinely
inclusive movement and be careful not to posit commonalities that mask
important ways in which women qua women differ. These
concerns (among others) have generated a situation where (as Linda
Alcoff puts it) feminists aim to speak and make political demands in
the name of women, at the same time rejecting the idea that there is a
unified category of women (2006, 152). If feminist critiques of the
category women are successful, then what (if anything) binds
women together, what is it to be a woman, and what kinds of demands
can feminists make on behalf of women?
Many have found the fragmentation of the category of women problematic
for political reasons (e.g. Alcoff 2006; Bach 2012; Benhabib 1992;
Frye 1996; Haslanger 2000b; Heyes 2000; Martin 1994; Mikkola 2007;
Stoljar 1995; Stone 2004; Tanesini 1996; Young 1997; Zack 2005). For
instance, Young holds that accounts like Spelman’s reduce the
category of women to a gerrymandered collection of individuals with
nothing to bind them together (1997, 20). Black women differ from
white women but members of both groups also differ from one another
with respect to nationality, ethnicity, class, sexual orientation and
economic position; that is, wealthy white women differ from
working-class white women due to their economic and class positions.
These sub-groups are themselves diverse: for instance, some
working-class white women in Northern Ireland are starkly divided
along religious lines. So if we accept Spelman’s position, we
risk ending up with individual women and nothing to bind them
together. And this is problematic: in order to respond to oppression
of women in general, feminists must understand them as a category in
some sense. Young writes that without doing so “it is not
possible to conceptualize oppression as a systematic, structured,
institutional process” (1997, 17). Some, then, take the
articulation of an inclusive category of women to be the prerequisite
for effective feminist politics and a rich literature has emerged that
aims to conceptualise women as a group or a collective (e.g. Alcoff
2006; Ásta 2011; Frye 1996; 2011; Haslanger 2000b; Heyes 2000;
Stoljar 1995, 2011; Young 1997; Zack 2005). Articulations of this
category can be divided into those that are: (a) gender nominalist
— positions that deny there is something women qua
women share and that seek to unify women’s social kind by
appealing to something external to women; and (b) gender realist
— positions that take there to be something women qua
women share (although these realist positions differ significantly
from those outlined in Section 2). Below we will review some
influential gender nominalist and gender realist positions. Before
doing so, it is worth noting that not everyone is convinced that
attempts to articulate an inclusive category of women can succeed or
that worries about what it is to be a woman are in need of being
resolved. Mikkola (2016) argues that feminist politics need not rely
on overcoming (what she calls) the ‘gender controversy’:
that feminists must settle the meaning of gender concepts and
articulate a way to ground women’s social kind membership. As
she sees it, disputes about ‘what it is to be a woman’
have become theoretically bankrupt and intractable, which has
generated an analytical impasse that looks unsurpassable. Instead,
Mikkola argues for giving up the quest, which in any case in her view
poses no serious political obstacles.
Elizabeth Barnes (2020) responds to the need to offer an inclusive
conception of gender somewhat differently, although she endorses the
need for feminism to be inclusive particularly of trans people. Barnes
holds that typically philosophical theories of gender aim to offer an
account of what it is to be a woman (or man, genderqueer, etc.), where
such an account is presumed to provide necessary and sufficient
conditions for being a woman or an account of our gender terms’
extensions. But, she holds, it is a mistake to expect our theories of
gender to do so. For Barnes, a project that offers a metaphysics of
gender “should be understood as the project of theorizing what
it is —if anything— about the social world that ultimately
explains gender” (2020, 706). This project is not equivalent to
one that aims to define gender terms or elucidate the application
conditions for natural language gender terms though.
4.1 Gender nominalism
4.1.1 Gendered social series
Iris Young argues that unless there is “some sense in which
‘woman’ is the name of a social collective [that feminism
represents], there is nothing specific to feminist politics”
(1997, 13). In order to make the category women intelligible,
she argues that women make up a series: a particular kind of social
collective “whose members are unified passively by the objects
their actions are oriented around and/or by the objectified results of
the material effects of the actions of the other” (Young 1997,
23). A series is distinct from a group in that, whereas members of
groups are thought to self-consciously share certain goals, projects,
traits and/ or self-conceptions, members of series pursue their own
individual ends without necessarily having anything at all in common.
Young holds that women are not bound together by a shared feature or
experience (or set of features and experiences) since she takes
Spelman’s particularity argument to have established definitely
that no such feature exists (1997, 13; see also: Frye 1996; Heyes
2000). Instead, women’s category is unified by certain
practico-inert realities or the ways in which women’s lives and
their actions are oriented around certain objects and everyday
realities (Young 1997, 23–4). For example, bus commuters make up
a series unified through their individual actions being organised
around the same practico-inert objects of the bus and the practice of
public transport. Women make up a series unified through women’s
lives and actions being organised around certain practico-inert
objects and realities that position them as women.
Young identifies two broad groups of such practico-inert objects and
realities. First, phenomena associated with female bodies (physical
facts), biological processes that take place in female bodies
(menstruation, pregnancy, childbirth) and social rules associated with
these biological processes (social rules of menstruation, for
instance). Second, gender-coded objects and practices: pronouns,
verbal and visual representations of gender, gender-coded artefacts
and social spaces, clothes, cosmetics, tools and furniture. So, women
make up a series since their lives and actions are organised around
female bodies and certain gender-coded objects. Their series is bound
together passively and the unity is “not one that arises from
the individuals called women” (Young 1997, 32).
Although Young’s proposal purports to be a response to
Spelman’s worries, Stone has questioned whether it is, after
all, susceptible to the particularity argument: ultimately, on
Young’s view, something women as women share (their
practico-inert realities) binds them together (Stone 2004).
4.1.2 Resemblance nominalism
Natalie Stoljar holds that unless the category of women is unified,
feminist action on behalf of women cannot be justified (1995, 282).
Stoljar too is persuaded by the thought that women qua women
do not share anything unitary. This prompts her to argue for
resemblance nominalism. This is the view that a certain kind of
resemblance relation holds between entities of a particular type (for
more on resemblance nominalism, see Armstrong 1989, 39–58).
Stoljar is not alone in arguing for resemblance relations to make
sense of women as a category; others have also done so, usually
appealing to Wittgenstein’s ‘family resemblance’
relations (Alcoff 1988; Green & Radford Curry 1991; Heyes 2000;
Munro 2006). Stoljar relies more on Price’s resemblance
nominalism whereby x is a member of some type F only
if x resembles some paradigm or exemplar of F
sufficiently closely (Price 1953, 20). For instance, the type of red
entities is unified by some chosen red paradigms so that only those
entities that sufficiently resemble the paradigms count as red. The
type (or category) of women, then, is unified by some chosen woman
paradigms so that those who sufficiently resemble the woman paradigms
count as women (Stoljar 1995, 284).
Semantic considerations about the concept woman suggest to
Stoljar that resemblance nominalism should be endorsed (Stoljar 2000,
28). It seems unlikely that the concept is applied on the basis of
some single social feature all and only women possess. By contrast,
woman is a cluster concept and our attributions of womanhood
pick out “different arrangements of features in different
individuals” (Stoljar 2000, 27). More specifically, they pick
out the following clusters of features: (a) Female sex; (b)
Phenomenological features: menstruation, female sexual experience,
child-birth, breast-feeding, fear of walking on the streets at night
or fear of rape; (c) Certain roles: wearing typically female clothing,
being oppressed on the basis of one’s sex or undertaking
care-work; (d) Gender attribution: “calling oneself a woman,
being called a woman” (Stoljar 1995, 283–4). For Stoljar,
attributions of womanhood are to do with a variety of traits and
experiences: those that feminists have historically termed
‘gender traits’ (like social, behavioural, psychological
traits) and those termed ‘sex traits’.
Nonetheless, she holds that since the concept woman applies
to (at least some) trans persons, one can be a woman without being
female (Stoljar 1995, 282).
The cluster concept woman does not, however,
straightforwardly provide the criterion for picking out the category
of women. Rather, the four clusters of features that the concept picks
out help single out woman paradigms that in turn help single out the
category of women. First, any individual who possesses a
feature from at least three of the four clusters mentioned
will count as an exemplar of the category. For instance, an
African-American with primary and secondary female sex
characteristics, who describes herself as a woman and is oppressed on
the basis of her sex, along with a white European hermaphrodite
brought up ‘as a girl’, who engages in female roles and
has female phenomenological features despite lacking female sex
characteristics, will count as woman paradigms (Stoljar 1995,
284).[7]
Second, any individual who resembles “any of the paradigms
sufficiently closely (on Price’s account, as closely as [the
paradigms] resemble each other) will be a member of the resemblance
class ‘woman’” (Stoljar 1995, 284). That is, what
delimits membership in the category of women is that one resembles
sufficiently a woman paradigm.
4.2 Neo-gender realism
4.2.1 Social subordination and gender
In a series of articles collected in her 2012 book, Sally Haslanger
argues for a way to define the concept woman that is
politically useful, serving as a tool in feminist fights against
sexism, and that shows woman to be a social (not a
biological) notion. More specifically, Haslanger argues that gender is
a matter of occupying either a subordinate or a privileged social
position. In some articles, Haslanger is arguing for a revisionary
analysis of the concept woman (2000b; 2003a; 2003b).
Elsewhere she suggests that her analysis may not be that revisionary
after all (2005; 2006). Consider the former argument first.
Haslanger’s analysis is, in her terms, ameliorative: it aims to
elucidate which gender concepts best help feminists achieve their
legitimate purposes thereby elucidating those concepts feminists
should be using (Haslanger 2000b,
33).[8]
Now, feminists need gender terminology in order to fight sexist
injustices (Haslanger 2000b, 36). In particular, they need gender
terms to identify, explain and talk about persistent social
inequalities between males and females. Haslanger’s analysis of
gender begins with the recognition that females and males differ in
two respects: physically and in their social positions. Societies in
general tend to “privilege individuals with male bodies”
(Haslanger 2000b, 38) so that the social positions they subsequently
occupy are better than the social positions of those with female
bodies. And this generates persistent sexist injustices. With this in
mind, Haslanger specifies how she understands genders:
S is a woman iff [by definition] S is
systematically subordinated along some dimension (economic, political,
legal, social, etc.), and S is ‘marked’ as a
target for this treatment by observed or imagined bodily features
presumed to be evidence of a female’s biological role in
reproduction.
S is a man iff [by definition] S is
systematically privileged along some dimension (economic, political,
legal, social, etc.), and S is ‘marked’ as a
target for this treatment by observed or imagined bodily features
presumed to be evidence of a male’s biological role in
reproduction. (2003a, 6–7)
These are constitutive of being a woman and a man:
what makes calling S a woman apt, is that S is
oppressed on sex-marked grounds; what makes calling S a man
apt, is that S is privileged on sex-marked grounds.
Haslanger’s ameliorative analysis is counterintuitive in that
females who are not sex-marked for oppression, do not count as women.
At least arguably, the Queen of England is not oppressed on sex-marked
grounds and so, would not count as a woman on Haslanger’s
definition. And, similarly, all males who are not privileged would not
count as men. This might suggest that Haslanger’s analysis
should be rejected in that it does not capture what language users
have in mind when applying gender terms. However, Haslanger argues
that this is not a reason to reject the definitions, which she takes
to be revisionary: they are not meant to capture our intuitive gender
terms. In response, Mikkola (2009) has argued that revisionary
analyses of gender concepts, like Haslanger’s, are both
politically unhelpful and philosophically unnecessary.
Note also that Haslanger’s proposal is eliminativist: gender
justice would eradicate gender, since it would abolish those sexist
social structures responsible for sex-marked oppression and privilege.
If sexist oppression were to cease, women and men would no longer
exist (although there would still be males and females). Not all
feminists endorse such an eliminativist view though. Stone holds that
Haslanger does not leave any room for positively revaluing what it is
to be a woman: since Haslanger defines woman in terms of
subordination,
any woman who challenges her subordinate status must by definition be
challenging her status as a woman, even if she does not intend to
… positive change to our gender norms would involve getting rid
of the (necessarily subordinate) feminine gender. (Stone 2007, 160)
But according to Stone this is not only undesirable – one should
be able to challenge subordination without having to challenge
one’s status as a woman. It is also false: “because norms
of femininity can be and constantly are being revised, women can be
women without thereby being subordinate” (Stone 2007, 162;
Mikkola [2016] too argues that Haslanger’s eliminativism is
troublesome).
Theodore Bach holds that Haslanger’s eliminativism is
undesirable on other grounds, and that Haslanger’s position
faces another more serious problem. Feminism faces the following
worries (among others):
Representation problem: “if there is no real group of
‘women’, then it is incoherent to make moral claims and
advance political policies on behalf of women” (Bach 2012,
234).
Commonality problems: (1) There is no feature that all women
cross-culturally and transhistorically share. (2) Delimiting
women’s social kind with the help of some essential property
privileges those who possess it, and marginalizes those who do not
(Bach 2012, 235).
According to Bach, Haslanger’s strategy to resolve these
problems appeals to ‘social objectivism’. First, we define
women “according to a suitably abstract relational
property” (Bach 2012, 236), which avoids the commonality
problems. Second, Haslanger employs “an ontologically thin
notion of ‘objectivity’” (Bach 2012, 236) that
answers the representation problem. Haslanger’s solution (Bach
holds) is specifically to argue that women make up an objective type
because women are objectively similar to one another, and not simply
classified together given our background conceptual schemes. Bach
claims though that Haslanger’s account is not objective enough,
and we should on political grounds “provide a stronger
ontological characterization of the genders men and
women according to which they are natural kinds with
explanatory essences” (Bach 2012, 238). He thus proposes that
women make up a natural kind with a historical essence:
The essential property of women, in virtue of which an individual is a
member of the kind ‘women,’ is participation in a lineage
of women. In order to exemplify this relational property, an
individual must be a reproduction of ancestral women, in which case
she must have undergone the ontogenetic processes through which a
historical gender system replicates women. (Bach 2012, 271)
In short, one is not a woman due to shared surface properties with
other women (like occupying a subordinate social position). Rather,
one is a woman because one has the right history: one has undergone
the ubiquitous ontogenetic process of gender socialization. Thinking
about gender in this way supposedly provides a stronger kind unity
than Haslanger’s that simply appeals to shared surface
properties.
Not everyone agrees; Mikkola (2020) argues that Bach’s
metaphysical picture has internal tensions that render it puzzling and
that Bach’s metaphysics does not provide good responses to the
commonality and presentation problems. The historically essentialist
view also has anti-trans implications. After all, trans women who have
not undergone female gender socialization won’t count as women
on his view (Mikkola [2016, 2020] develops this line of critique in
more detail). More worryingly, trans women will count as men contrary
to their self-identification. Both Bettcher (2013) and Jenkins (2016)
consider the importance of gender self-identification. Bettcher argues
that there is more than one ‘correct’ way to understand
womanhood: at the very least, the dominant (mainstream), and the
resistant (trans) conceptions. Dominant views like that of
Bach’s tend to erase trans people’s experiences and to
marginalize trans women within feminist movements. Rather than trans
women having to defend their self-identifying claims, these claims
should be taken at face value right from the start. And so, Bettcher
holds, “in analyzing the meaning of terms such as
‘woman,’ it is inappropriate to dismiss alternative ways
in which those terms are actually used in trans subcultures; such
usage needs to be taken into consideration as part of the
analysis” (2013, 235).
Specifically with Haslanger in mind and in a similar vein, Jenkins
(2016) discusses how Haslanger’s revisionary approach unduly
excludes some trans women from women’s social kind. On
Jenkins’s view, Haslanger’s ameliorative methodology in
fact yields more than one satisfying target concept: one that
“corresponds to Haslanger’s proposed concept and captures
the sense of gender as an imposed social class”; another that
“captures the sense of gender as a lived identity”
(Jenkins 2016, 397). The latter of these allows us to include trans
women into women’s social kind, who on Haslanger’s social
class approach to gender would inappropriately have been excluded.
(See Andler 2017 for the view that Jenkins’s purportedly
inclusive conception of gender is still not fully inclusive. Jenkins
2018 responds to this charge and develops the notion of gender
identity still further.)
In addition to her revisionary argument, Haslanger has suggested that
her ameliorative analysis of woman may not be as revisionary
as it first seems (2005, 2006). Although successful in their reference
fixing, ordinary language users do not always know precisely what they
are talking about. Our language use may be skewed by oppressive
ideologies that can “mislead us about the content of our own
thoughts” (Haslanger 2005, 12). Although her gender terminology
is not intuitive, this could simply be because oppressive ideologies
mislead us about the meanings of our gender terms. Our everyday gender
terminology might mean something utterly different from what we
think it means; and we could be entirely ignorant of this.
Perhaps Haslanger’s analysis, then, has captured our everyday
gender vocabulary revealing to us the terms that we actually employ:
we may be applying ‘woman’ in our everyday language on the
basis of sex-marked subordination whether we take ourselves to be
doing so or not. If this is so, Haslanger’s gender terminology
is not radically revisionist.
Saul (2006) argues that, despite it being possible that we unknowingly
apply ‘woman’ on the basis of social subordination, it is
extremely difficult to show that this is the case. This would require
showing that the gender terminology we in fact employ is
Haslanger’s proposed gender terminology. But discovering the
grounds on which we apply everyday gender terms is extremely difficult
precisely because they are applied in various and idiosyncratic ways
(Saul 2006, 129). Haslanger, then, needs to do more in order to show
that her analysis is non-revisionary.
4.2.2 Gender uniessentialism
Charlotte Witt (2011a; 2011b) argues for a particular sort of gender
essentialism, which Witt terms ‘uniessentialism’. Her
motivation and starting point is the following: many ordinary social
agents report gender being essential to them and claim that they would
be a different person were they of a different sex/gender.
Uniessentialism attempts to understand and articulate this. However,
Witt’s work departs in important respects from the earlier
(so-called) essentialist or gender realist positions discussed in
Section 2: Witt does not posit some essential property of womanhood of
the kind discussed above, which failed to take women’s
differences into account. Further, uniessentialism differs
significantly from those position developed in response to the problem
of how we should conceive of women’s social kind. It is not
about solving the standard dispute between gender nominalists and
gender realists, or about articulating some supposedly shared property
that binds women together and provides a theoretical ground for
feminist political solidarity. Rather, uniessentialism aims to make
good the widely held belief that gender is constitutive of who we
are.[9]
Uniessentialism is a sort of individual essentialism. Traditionally
philosophers distinguish between kind and individual essentialisms:
the former examines what binds members of a kind together and what do
all members of some kind have in common qua members of that
kind. The latter asks: what makes an individual the
individual it is. We can further distinguish two sorts of individual
essentialisms: Kripkean identity essentialism and Aristotelian
uniessentialism. The former asks: what makes an individual
that individual? The latter, however, asks a slightly
different question: what explains the unity of individuals? What
explains that an individual entity exists over and above the sum total
of its constituent parts? (The standard feminist debate over gender
nominalism and gender realism has largely been about kind
essentialism. Being about individual essentialism, Witt’s
uniessentialism departs in an important way from the standard debate.)
From the two individual essentialisms, Witt endorses the Aristotelian
one. On this view, certain functional essences have a unifying role:
these essences are responsible for the fact that material parts
constitute a new individual, rather than just a lump of stuff or a
collection of particles. Witt’s example is of a house: the
essential house-functional property (what the entity is for, what its
purpose is) unifies the different material parts of a house so that
there is a house, and not just a collection of house-constituting
particles (2011a, 6). Gender (being a woman/a man) functions in a
similar fashion and provides “the principle of normative
unity” that organizes, unifies and determines the roles of
social individuals (Witt 2011a, 73). Due to this, gender is a
uniessential property of social individuals.
It is important to clarify the notions of gender and
social individuality that Witt employs. First, gender is a
social position that “cluster[s] around the engendering function
… women conceive and bear … men beget” (Witt
2011a, 40). These are women and men’s socially mediated
reproductive functions (Witt 2011a, 29) and they differ from the
biological function of reproduction, which roughly corresponds to sex
on the standard sex/gender distinction. Witt writes: “to be a
woman is to be recognized to have a particular function in
engendering, to be a man is to be recognized to have a different
function in engendering” (2011a, 39). Second, Witt distinguishes
persons (those who possess self-consciousness), human
beings (those who are biologically human) and social
individuals (those who occupy social positions synchronically and
diachronically). These ontological categories are not equivalent in
that they possess different persistence and identity conditions.
Social individuals are bound by social normativity, human beings by
biological normativity. These normativities differ in two respects:
first, social norms differ from one culture to the next whereas
biological norms do not; second, unlike biological normativity, social
normativity requires “the recognition by others that an agent is
both responsive to and evaluable under a social norm” (Witt
2011a, 19). Thus, being a social individual is not equivalent to being
a human being. Further, Witt takes personhood to be defined in terms
of intrinsic psychological states of self-awareness and
self-consciousness. However, social individuality is defined in terms
of the extrinsic feature of occupying a social position, which depends
for its existence on a social world. So, the two are not equivalent:
personhood is essentially about intrinsic features and could exist
without a social world, whereas social individuality is essentially
about extrinsic features that could not exist without a social
world.
Witt’s gender essentialist argument crucially pertains to
social individuals, not to persons or human beings: saying
that persons or human beings are gendered would be a category mistake.
But why is gender essential to social individuals? For Witt, social
individuals are those who occupy positions in social reality. Further,
“social positions have norms or social roles associated with
them; a social role is what an individual who occupies a given social
position is responsive to and evaluable under” (Witt 2011a, 59).
However, qua social individuals, we occupy multiple social
positions at once and over time: we can be women, mothers, immigrants,
sisters, academics, wives, community organisers and team-sport coaches
synchronically and diachronically. Now, the issue for Witt is what
unifies these positions so that a social individual is
constituted. After all, a bundle of social position occupancies does
not make for an individual (just as a bundle of properties like
being white, cube-shaped and sweet do not
make for a sugar cube). For Witt, this unifying role is undertaken by
gender (being a woman or a man): it is
a pervasive and fundamental social position that unifies and
determines all other social positions both synchronically and
diachronically. It unifies them not physically, but by providing a
principle of normative unity. (2011a, 19–20)
By ‘normative unity’, Witt means the following: given our
social roles and social position occupancies, we are responsive to
various sets of social norms. These norms are “complex patterns
of behaviour and practices that constitute what one ought to do in a
situation given one’s social position(s) and one’s social
context” (Witt 2011a, 82). The sets of norms can conflict: the
norms of motherhood can (and do) conflict with the norms of being an
academic philosopher. However, in order for this conflict to exist,
the norms must be binding on a single social individual.
Witt, then, asks: what explains the existence and unity of the social
individual who is subject to conflicting social norms? The answer is
gender.
Gender is not just a social role that unifies social individuals. Witt
takes it to be the social role — as she puts it, it is
the mega social role that unifies social agents. First,
gender is a mega social role if it satisfies two conditions (and Witt
claims that it does): (1) if it provides the principle of synchronic
and diachronic unity of social individuals, and (2) if it inflects and
defines a broad range of other social roles. Gender satisfies the
first in usually being a life-long social position: a social
individual persists just as long as their gendered social position
persists. Further, Witt maintains, trans people are not
counterexamples to this claim: transitioning entails that the old
social individual has ceased to exist and a new one has come into
being. And this is consistent with the same person persisting and
undergoing social individual change via transitioning. Gender
satisfies the second condition too. It inflects other social roles,
like being a parent or a professional. The expectations attached to
these social roles differ depending on the agent’s gender, since
gender imposes different social norms to govern the execution of the
further social roles. Now, gender — as opposed to some other
social category, like race — is not just a mega social role; it
is the unifying mega social role. Cross-cultural and trans-historical
considerations support this view. Witt claims that patriarchy is a
social universal (2011a, 98). By contrast, racial categorisation
varies historically and cross-culturally, and racial oppression is not
a universal feature of human cultures. Thus, gender has a better claim
to being the social role that is uniessential to social individuals.
This account of gender essentialism not only explains social
agents’ connectedness to their gender, but it also provides a
helpful way to conceive of women’s agency — something that
is central to feminist politics.
4.2.3 Gender as positionality
Linda Alcoff holds that feminism faces an identity crisis: the
category of women is feminism’s starting point, but various
critiques about gender have fragmented the category and it is not
clear how feminists should understand what it is to be a woman (2006,
chapter 5). In response, Alcoff develops an account of gender as
positionality whereby “gender is, among other things, a
position one occupies and from which one can act politically”
(2006, 148). In particular, she takes one’s social position to
foster the development of specifically gendered identities (or
self-conceptions): “The very subjectivity (or subjective
experience of being a woman) and the very identity of women are
constituted by women’s position” (Alcoff 2006, 148).
Alcoff holds that there is an objective basis for distinguishing
individuals on the grounds of (actual or expected) reproductive
roles:
Women and men are differentiated by virtue of their different
relationship of possibility to biological reproduction, with
biological reproduction referring to conceiving, giving birth, and
breast-feeding, involving one’s body. (Alcoff 2006, 172,
italics in original)
The thought is that those standardly classified as biologically
female, although they may not actually be able to reproduce, will
encounter “a different set of practices, expectations, and
feelings in regard to reproduction” than those standardly
classified as male (Alcoff 2006, 172). Further, this differential
relation to the possibility of reproduction is used as the basis for
many cultural and social phenomena that position women and men: it can
be
the basis of a variety of social segregations, it can engender the
development of differential forms of embodiment experienced throughout
life, and it can generate a wide variety of affective responses, from
pride, delight, shame, guilt, regret, or great relief from having
successfully avoided reproduction. (Alcoff 2006, 172)
Reproduction, then, is an objective basis for distinguishing
individuals that takes on a cultural dimension in that it positions
women and men differently: depending on the kind of body one has,
one’s lived experience will differ. And this fosters the
construction of gendered social identities: one’s role in
reproduction helps configure how one is socially positioned and this
conditions the development of specifically gendered social
identities.
Since women are socially positioned in various different contexts,
“there is no gender essence all women share” (Alcoff 2006,
147–8). Nonetheless, Alcoff acknowledges that her account is
akin to the original 1960s sex/gender distinction insofar as sex
difference (understood in terms of the objective division of
reproductive labour) provides the foundation for certain cultural
arrangements (the development of a gendered social identity). But,
with the benefit of hindsight
we can see that maintaining a distinction between the objective
category of sexed identity and the varied and culturally contingent
practices of gender does not presume an absolute distinction of the
old-fashioned sort between culture and a reified nature. (Alcoff 2006,
175)
That is, her view avoids the implausible claim that sex is exclusively
to do with nature and gender with culture. Rather, the distinction on
the basis of reproductive possibilities shapes and is shaped by the
sorts of cultural and social phenomena (like varieties of social
segregation) these possibilities gives rise to. For instance,
technological interventions can alter sex differences illustrating
that this is the case (Alcoff 2006, 175). Women’s specifically
gendered social identities that are constituted by their context
dependent positions, then, provide the starting point for feminist
politics.
5. Beyond the Binary
Recently Robin Dembroff (2020) has argued that existing metaphysical
accounts of gender fail to address non-binary gender identities. This
generates two concerns. First, metaphysical accounts of gender (like
the ones outlined in previous sections) are insufficient for capturing
those who reject binary gender categorisation where people are either
men or women. In so doing, these accounts are not satisfying as
explanations of gender understood in a more expansive sense that goes
beyond the binary. Second, the failure to understand non-binary gender
identities contributes to a form of
epistemic injustice
called ‘hermeneutical injustice’: it feeds into a
collective failure to comprehend and analyse concepts and practices
that undergird non-binary classification schemes, thereby impeding on
one’s ability to fully understand themselves. To overcome these
problems, Dembroff suggests an account of genderqueer that they call
‘critical gender kind’:
a kind whose members collectively destabilize one or more elements of
dominant gender ideology. Genderqueer, on my proposed model, is a
category whose members collectively destabilize the binary axis, or
the idea that the only possible genders are the exclusive and
exhaustive kinds men and women. (2020, 2)
Note that Dembroff’s position is not to be confused with
‘gender critical feminist’ positions like those noted
above, which are critical of the prevalent feminist focus on gender,
as opposed to sex, kinds. Dembroff understands genderqueer as a gender
kind, but one that is critical of dominant binary understandings of
gender.
Dembroff identifies two modes of destabilising the gender binary:
principled and existential. Principled destabilising “stems from
or otherwise expresses individuals’ social or political
commitments regarding gender norms, practices, and structures”,
while existential destabilising “stems from or otherwise
expresses individuals’ felt or desired gender roles, embodiment,
and/or categorization” (2020, 13). These modes are not mutually
exclusive, and they can help us understand the difference between
allies and members of genderqueer kinds: “While both resist
dominant gender ideology, members of [genderqueer] kinds resist (at
least in part) due to felt or desired gender categorization that
deviates from dominant expectations, norms, and assumptions”
(2020, 14). These modes of destabilisation also enable us to formulate
an understanding of non-critical gender kinds that binary
understandings of women and men’s kinds exemplify. Dembroff
defines these kinds as follows:
For a given kind X, X is a non-critical gender
kind relative to a given society iff X’s members
collectively restabilize one or more elements of the dominant gender
ideology in that society. (2020, 14)
Dembroff’s understanding of critical and non-critical gender
kinds importantly makes gender kind membership something more and
other than a mere psychological phenomenon. To engage in collectively
destabilising or restabilising dominant gender normativity and
ideology, we need more than mere attitudes or mental states –
resisting or maintaining such normativity requires action as well. In
so doing, Dembroff puts their position forward as an alternative to
two existing internalist positions about gender. First, to Jennifer
McKitrick’s (2015) view whereby gender is dispositional: in a
context where someone is disposed to behave in ways that would be
taken by others to be indicative of (e.g.) womanhood, the person has a
woman’s gender identity. Second, to Jenkin’s (2016, 2018)
position that takes an individual’s gender identity to be
dependent on which gender-specific norms the person experiences as
being relevant to them. On this view, someone is a woman if the person
experiences norms associated with women to be relevant to the person
in the particular social context that they are in. Neither of these
positions well-captures non-binary identities, Dembroff argues, which
motivates the account of genderqueer identities as critical gender
kinds.
As Dembroff acknowledges, substantive philosophical work on non-binary
gender identities is still developing. However, it is important to
note that analytic philosophers are beginning to engage in gender
metaphysics that goes beyond the binary.
6. Conclusion
This entry first looked at feminist objections to biological
determinism and the claim that gender is socially constructed. Next,
it examined feminist critiques of prevalent understandings of gender
and sex, and the distinction itself. In response to these concerns,
the entry looked at how a unified women’s category could be
articulated for feminist political purposes. This illustrated that
gender metaphysics — or what it is to be a woman or a
man or a genderqueer person — is still very much a live issue.
And although contemporary feminist philosophical debates have
questioned some of the tenets and details of the original 1960s
sex/gender distinction, most still hold onto the view that gender is
about social factors and that it is (in some sense) distinct
from biological sex. The jury is still out on what the best, the most
useful, or (even) the correct definition of gender is.
Bibliography
Alcoff, L., 1988, “Cultural Feminism Versus
Post-Structuralism: The Identity Crisis in Feminist Theory”,
Signs, 13: 405–436.
–––, 2006, Visible Identities, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Andler, M., 2017, “Gender Identity and Exclusion: A Reply to
Jenkins”, Ethics, 127: 883–895.
Ásta (Sveinsdóttir), 2011, “The Metaphysics of
Sex and Gender”, in Feminist Metaphysics, C. Witt
(ed.), Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 47–65.
–––, 2018, Categories We Live By: The
Construction of Sex, Gender, Race, and Other Social Categories,
New York: Oxford University Press.
Ayala, S. and Vasilyeva, N., 2015, “Extended Sex: An Account
of Sex for a More Just Society”, Hypatia, 30:
725–742.
Antony, L., 1998, “‘Human Nature’ and Its Role
in Feminist Theory”, in Philosophy in a Feminist Voice,
J. Kourany (ed.), New Haven: Princeton University Press, pp.
63–91.
Armstrong, D., 1989, Universals: An Opinionated
Introduction, Boulder, CO: Westview.
Bach, T., 2012, “Gender is a Natural Kind with a Historical
Essence”, Ethics, 122: 231–272.
Barnes, E., 2020, “Gender and Gender Terms”,
Noûs, 54: 704–730.
de Beauvoir, S., 1972, The Second Sex, Harmondsworth:
Penguin.
Benhabib, S., 1992, Situating the Self, New York:
Routledge.
Bettcher, T.M., 2013, “Trans Women and the Meaning of
‘Woman’”, in The Philosophy of Sex, N.
Power, R. Halwani, and A. Soble (eds.), Lanham, MD: Rowman and
Littlefield Publishers, Inc, pp. 233–250.
Bogardus, T., 2020, “Evaluating Arguments for the Sex/Gender
Distinction”, Philosophia, 48: 873–892.
Butler, J., 1990, “Performative Acts and Gender
Constitution”, in Performing Feminisms, S-E. Case
(ed.), Baltimore: John Hopkins University, pp. 270–282.
–––, 1991, “Contingent Foundations:
Feminism and the Question of ‘Postmodernism’”,
Praxis International, 11: 150–165.
–––, 1993, Bodies that Matter, London:
Routledge.
–––, 1997, The Psychic Life of Power,
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
–––, 1999, Gender Trouble, London:
Routledge, 2nd edition.
Byrne, A., 2020, “Are Women Adult Human Females?”,
Philosophical Studies, 177: 3783–3803.
–––, 2021, “Gender Muddle: Reply to
Dembroff”, Journal of Controversial Ideas, 1:
1–24.
Campbell, A., 2002, A Mind of One’s Own: The
Evolutionary Psychology of Women, Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Chodorow, N., 1978, Reproducing Mothering, Berkeley:
University of California Press.
–––, 1995, “Family Structure and Feminine
Personality”, in Feminism and Philosophy, N. Tuana, and
R. Tong (eds.), Boulder, CO: Westview, pp. 43–66.
Deaux, K. and B. Major, 1990, “A Social-Psychological Model
of Gender”, in Theoretical Perspectives on Sexual
Difference, D. Rhode (ed.), New Haven: Yale University Press, pp.
89-99.
Dembroff, R., 2020, “Beyond Binary: Genderqueer as Critical
Gender Kind”, Philosopher’s Imprint, 20:
1–23.
–––, 2021, “Escaping the Natural Attitude
about Gender”, Philosophical Studies, 178:
983–1003.
Fausto-Sterling, A., 1993a, Myths of Gender: Biological
Theories about Women and Men, New York: Basic Books,
2nd edition.
–––, 1993b, “The Five Sexes: Why Male and
Female are Not Enough”, The Sciences, 33:
20–24.
–––, 2000a, “The Five Sexes:
Revisited”, The Sciences, July/August:
18–23.
–––, 2000b, Sexing the Body, New York:
Basic Books.
–––, 2003, “The Problem with Sex/Gender
and Nature/Nurture”, in Debating Biology: Sociological
Reflections on Health, Medicine and Society, S. J. Williams, L.
Birke, and G. A. Bendelow (eds.), London & New York: Routledge,
pp. 133–142.
–––, 2005, “The Bare Bones of Sex: Part 1
– Sex and Gender”, Signs, 30:
1491–1527.
Friedan, B., 1963, Feminine Mystique, Harmondsworth:
Penguin Books Ltd.
Frye, M., 1996, “The Necessity of Differences: Constructing
a Positive Category of Women”, Signs, 21:
991–1010.
–––, 2011, “Metaphors of Being a
φ”, in Feminist Metaphysics, C. Witt (ed.),
Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 85–95.
Gatens, M., 1996, Imaginary Bodies, London:
Routledge.
Gorman, C. 1992, “Sizing up the Sexes”, Time,
January 20: 42–51.
Green, J. M. and B. Radford Curry, 1991, “Recognizing Each
Other Amidst Diversity: Beyond Essentialism in Collaborative
Multi-Cultural Feminist Theory”, Sage, 8:
39–49.
Grosz, E., 1994, Volatile Bodies: Toward a Corporeal
Feminism, Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press.
Harris, A., 1993, “Race and Essentialism in Feminist Legal
Theory”, in Feminist Legal Theory: Foundations, D. K.
Weisberg (ed.), Philadelphia: Temple University Press, pp.
248–258.
Haslanger, S., 1995, “Ontology and Social
Construction”, Philosophical Topics, 23:
95–125.
–––, 2000a, “Feminism in Metaphysics:
Negotiating the Natural”, in Feminism in Philosophy, M.
Fricker, and J. Hornsby (eds.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
pp. 107–126.
–––, 2000b, “Gender and Race: (What) are
They? (What) Do We Want Them To Be?”, Noûs, 34:
31–55.
–––, 2003a, “Future Genders? Future
Races?”, Philosophic Exchange, 34: 4–27.
–––, 2003b, “Social Construction: The
‘Debunking’ Project”, in Socializing
Metaphysics: The Nature of Social Reality, F. Schmitt (ed.),
Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers Inc, pp.
301–325.
–––, 2005, “What Are We Talking About? The
Semantics and Politics of Social Kinds”, Hypatia, 20:
10–26.
–––, 2006, “What Good are Our
Intuitions?”, Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society,
Supplementary Volume 80: 89–118.
–––, 2012, Resisting Reality, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Heyes, C., 2000, Line Drawings, Ithaca & London:
Cornell University Press.
hooks, b., 2000, Feminist Theory: From Margins to Center,
London: Pluto, 2nd edition.
Jaggar, A., 1983, “Human Biology in Feminist Theory: Sexual
Equality Reconsidered”, in Beyond Domination: New
Perspectives on Women and Philosophy, C. Gould (ed.), Lanham, MD:
Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Inc, pp. 21–42.
Jenkins, K., 2016, “Amelioration and Inclusion: Gender
Identity and the Concept of Woman”, Ethics, 126:
394–421.
–––, 2018, “Toward an Account of Gender
Identity”, Ergo, 5: 713–744.
Kimmel, M., 2000, The Gendered Society, New York: Oxford
University Press.
King, H., 2013, The One-Sex Body on Trial: The Classical and
Early Modern Evidence, Farnham: Ashgate Publishing, Ltd.
Laqueur, T., 1990, Making Sex: Body and Gender from the Greeks
to Freud, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Lawford-Smith, H., 2021, “Ending Sex-Based Oppression:
Transitional Pathways”, Philosophia, 49:
1021–1041.
Lloyd, G., 1993, The Man of Reason: ‘Male’ and
‘Female’ in Western Philosophy, London: Routledge,
2nd edition.
MacKinnon, C., 1989, Toward a Feminist Theory of State,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Martin, J. R. 1994, “Methodological Essentialism, False
Difference, and Other Dangerous Traps”, Signs, 19:
630–655.
McKitrick, J., 2015, “A Dispositional Account of
Gender”, Philosophical Studies, 172:
2575–2589.
Mikkola, M. 2006, “Elizabeth Spelman, Gender Realism, and
Women”, Hypatia, 21: 77–96.
–––, 2007, “Gender Sceptics and Feminist
Politics”, Res Publica, 13: 361–380.
–––, 2009, “Gender Concepts and
Intuitions”, Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 9:
559–583.
–––, 2011, “Ontological Commitments, Sex
and Gender”, in Feminist Metaphysics, C. Witt (ed.),
Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 67–84.
–––, 2016, The Wrong of Injustice:
Dehumanization and its Role in Feminist Philosophy, New York:
Oxford University Press.
–––, 2020, “The Function of Gender as a
Historical Kind”, in Social Functions in Philosophy:
Metaphysical, Normative, and Methodological Perspectives, R.
Hufendiek, D. James, and R. van Riel (eds.), London: Routledge, pp.
159–182.
Millett, K., 1971, Sexual Politics, London: Granada
Publishing Ltd.
Moi, T., 1999, What is a Woman?, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Munro, V., 2006, “Resemblances of Identity: Ludwig
Wittgenstein and Contemporary Feminist Legal Theory”, Res
Publica, 12: 137–162.
Nicholson, L., 1994, “Interpreting Gender”,
Signs, 20: 79–105.
–––, 1998, “Gender”, in A
Companion to Feminist Philosophy, A. Jaggar, and I. M. Young
(eds.), Malden, MA: Blackwell, pp. 289–297.
Price, H. H., 1953, Thinking and Experience, London:
Hutchinson’s University Library.
Prokhovnik, R., 1999, Rational Woman, London:
Routledge.
Rapaport, E. 2002, “Generalizing Gender: Reason and Essence
in the Legal Thought of Catharine MacKinnon”, in A Mind of
One’s Own: Feminist Essays on Reason and Objectivity, L. M.
Antony and C. E. Witt (eds.), Boulder, CO: Westview, 2nd
edition, pp. 254–272.
Renzetti, C. and D. Curran, 1992, “Sex-Role
Socialization”, in Feminist Philosophies, J. Kourany,
J. Sterba, and R. Tong (eds.), New Jersey: Prentice Hall, pp.
31–47.
Rogers, L., 1999, Sexing the Brain, London: Phoenix.
Rubin, G., 1975, “The Traffic in Women: Notes on the
‘Political Economy’ of Sex”, in Toward an
Anthropology of Women, R. Reiter (ed.), New York: Monthly Review
Press, pp. 157–210.
Salih, S., 2002, Judith Butler, London: Routledge.
Saul, J., 2006, “Gender and Race”, Proceedings of
the Aristotelian Society (Supplementary Volume), 80:
119–143.
Spelman, E., 1988, Inessential Woman, Boston: Beacon
Press.
Stoljar, N., 1995, “Essence, Identity and the Concept of
Woman”, Philosophical Topics, 23: 261–293.
–––, 2000, “The Politics of Identity and
the Metaphysics of Diversity”, in Proceedings of the
20th World Congress of Philosophy, D. Dahlstrom (ed.),
Bowling Green: Bowling Green State University, pp. 21–30.
–––, 2011, “Different Women. Gender and
the Realism-Nominalism Debate”, in Feminist
Metaphysics, C. Witt (ed.), Dordrecht: Springer, pp.
27–46.
Stoller, R. J., 1968, Sex and Gender: On The Development of
Masculinity and Femininity, New York: Science House.
Stone, A., 2004, “Essentialism and Anti-Essentialism in
Feminist Philosophy”, Journal of Moral Philosophy, 1:
135–153.
–––, 2007, An Introduction to Feminist
Philosophy, Cambridge: Polity.
Tanesini, A., 1996, “Whose Language?”, in Women,
Knowledge and Reality, A. Garry and M. Pearsall (eds.), London:
Routledge, pp. 353–365.
Witt, C., 1995, “Anti-Essentialism in Feminist
Theory”, Philosophical Topics, 23: 321–344.
–––, 2011a, The Metaphysics of Gender,
Oxford: Oxford University Press.
–––, 2011b, “What is Gender
Essentialism?”, in Feminist Metaphysics, C. Witt (ed.),
Dordrecht: Springer, pp. 11–25.
Wittig, M., 1992, The Straight Mind and Other Essays,
Boston: Beacon Press.
Young, I. M., 1997, “Gender as Seriality: Thinking about
Women as a Social Collective”, in Intersecting Voices,
I. M. Young, Princeton: Princeton University Press, pp.
12–37.
Zack, N., 2005, Inclusive Feminism, Lanham, MD: Rowman
& Littlefield.
Academic Tools
How to cite this entry.
Preview the PDF version of this entry at the
Friends of the SEP Society.
Look up topics and thinkers related to this entry
at the Internet Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO).
Enhanced bibliography for this entry
at PhilPapers, with links to its database.
Other Internet Resources
The Feminist Philosophers Blog
History of Sexuality Resources
(Duke Special Collections)
QueerTheory.com,
from the Internet Archive
World Wide Web Review: Webs of Transgender
What is Judith Butler’s Theory of Gender Performativity?
(Perlego, open access study guide/ introduction)
Related Entries
Beauvoir, Simone de |
feminist philosophy, approaches: intersections between analytic and continental philosophy |
feminist philosophy, topics: perspectives on reproduction and the family |
feminist philosophy, topics: perspectives on the self |
homosexuality |
identity politics |
speech acts
Acknowledgments
I am very grateful to Tuukka Asplund, Jenny Saul, Alison Stone and
Nancy Tuana for their extremely helpful and detailed comments when
writing this entry.
Copyright © 2022 by
Mari Mikkola
Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative.
The Encyclopedia Now Needs Your Support
Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free
Browse
Table of Contents
What's New
Random Entry
Chronological
Archives
About
Editorial Information
About the SEP
Editorial Board
How to Cite the SEP
Special Characters
Advanced Tools
Accessibility
Contact
Support SEP
Support the SEP
PDFs for SEP Friends
Make a Donation
SEPIA for Libraries
Mirror Sites
View this site from another server:
USA (Main Site)
Philosophy, Stanford University
Info about mirror sites
The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2024 by The Metaphysics Research Lab, Department of Philosophy, Stanford University
Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054
How femininity has changed over the past 50 years, according to a new study | The Independent | The Independent
femininity has changed over the past 50 years, according to a new study | The Independent | The Independent Jump to contentAsia EditionChangeUK EditionUS EditionEdición en EspañolSign up to our newslettersSubscribe nowLog in / Register IndependentBig in America Push notificationsSubscribeMenuNewsNewsUKUSWorldUK PoliticsBrexitHealthBusinessScienceSpaceNews VideosSportSportFootballParis 2024 OlympicsFormula 1Rugby UnionCricketTennisBoxingUFCCyclingGolfBettingSport VideosVoicesVoicesEditorialsLettersJohn RentoulMary DejevskyAndrew GriceSean O’GradyCultureCultureFilmTV & RadioMusicGamesBooksArtPhotographyTheatre & DanceCulture VideosLifestyleLifestyleShoppingTechMoneyFood & DrinkFashionLove & SexWomenHealth & FamiliesRoyal FamilyMotoringElectric Vehicles Lifestyle VideosTravelTravelUK Hotel ReviewsNews & AdviceSimon CalderCruisesUKEuropeUSAAsiaAustralia & New ZealandSouth AmericaC. America & CaribbeanMiddle EastPremiumPremiumEditorialsVoicesLong ReadsPolitics ExplainedNews AnalysisToday’s EditionMoreBestAdvisorHome & GardenTechFashion & BeautyFood & DrinkKidsBooksTravel & OutdoorsSports & FitnessDealsClimateNewsVoicesSustainable LivingExplainedClimate VideosElectric Vehicles SGITVBehind The HeadlinesOn The GroundDecomplicatedYou Ask The QuestionsBinge WatchMusic BoxLove LivesTravel SmartWatch on your TVToday’s EditionCrosswords & PuzzlesMost CommentedNewslettersAsk Me AnythingVirtual EventsBetting Sites Online Casinos Wine Offers VouchersIndy100Thank you for registeringPlease refresh the page or navigate to another page on the site to be automatically logged inPlease refresh your browser to be logged inLifestyleHow femininity has changed over the past 50 years, according to a new studyWomen are no longer so concerned with being delicate, caring and sweetRachel HosieTuesday 25 September 2018 13:54 BSTCommentsArticle bookmarkedFind your bookmarks in your Independent Premium section, under my profileDon't show me this message again✕Stay ahead of the trend in fashion and beyond with our free weekly Lifestyle Edit newsletterStay ahead of the trend in fashion and beyond with our free weekly Lifestyle Edit newsletter Please enter a valid email addressPlease enter a valid email addressSIGN UPI would like to be emailed about offers, events and updates from The Independent. Read our privacy noticeFemininity today is associated with being independent, outspoken, compassionate and kind, a new study has found.The research reveals how the idea of femininity has evolved over the decades - 50 years ago, 53 per cent of people said to be feminine meant to be “a good mother and caring", while 41 per cent of people considered being “delicate and sweet” an essential part of being a woman.Now, however, attitudes have evolved, as the study of 2,000 women by Always Platinum reveals. RecommendedOver half of millennial women don’t identify as feminist - here's whyToday, women are striving to show compassion and kindness, be good friends and promote other females in the workplace.More than half (58 per cent) of UK females describe the modern woman as independent, 48 per cent as resilient and 44 per cent as ambitious.The study also found that 26 per cent of people believe it’s in their 30s that women find the perfect balance of being soft and strong - almost nine in 10 believe it’s possible to be assertive and get what you want in life whilst still being caring.The research confirms what many people will have already known about how the notion of femininity has evolved. As society makes positive steps towards gender equality, what it means to be masculine has also come under scrutiny.Many people have made strides to debunk concept of ‘toxic masculinity’ - the idea that being a man involves being aggressive, stoic and dominant over women.One of the ways this has been seen is through men speaking out about their mental health - influencers such as Ben Bidwell are leading the charge, arguing that the phrase “man up” is problematic.As what it means to be feminine evolves, masculinity seems to be developing too.More aboutfemininityJoin our commenting forumJoin thought-provoking conversations, follow other Independent readers and see their repliesComments1/1How femininity has changed over the past 50 yearsHow femininity has changed over the past 50 yearsWomen are no longer so concerned with being delicate, caring and sweet✕Subscribe to Independent Premium to bookmark this articleWant to bookmark your favourite articles and stories to read or reference later? Start your Independent Premium subscription today.SubscribeAlready subscribed? Log inMost PopularPopular videosSponsored FeaturesGet in touchContact usOur ProductsSubscribeRegisterNewslettersToday’s EditionInstall our appArchiveOther publicationsInternational editionsIndependent en EspañolIndependent ArabiaIndependent TurkishIndependent PersianIndependent UrduEvening StandardExtrasAdvisorPuzzlesAll topicsBetting OffersVoucher codesCompetitions and offersIndependent AdvertisingIndependent IgniteSyndicationWorking at The IndependentLegalCode of conduct and complaintsContributorsCookie policyPrivacy noticeUser policiesModern Slavery ActThank you for registeringPlease refresh the page or navigate to another page on the site to be automatically logged inPlease refresh your browser to be logged inCloseAsia EditionChangeUK EditionUS EditionEdición en EspañolSubscribeLog in / RegisterBig in America Push notifications Today’s EditionCrosswords & PuzzlesMost CommentedNewslettersAsk Me AnythingVirtual EventsBetting Sites Online Casinos Wine Offers VouchersIndy100✕Log inEmail addressPasswordEmail and password don't matchSubmitForgotten your password?New to The Independent?RegisterOr if you would prefer:SIGN IN WITH GOOGLEWant an ad-free experience?View offersThis site is protected by reCAPTCHA and the Google Privacy notice and Terms of service apply.My Independent PremiumAccount detailsHelp centreLogouPage restricted | ScienceDirect
Page restricted | ScienceDirect
Your Browser is out of date.
Update your browser to view ScienceDirect.
View recommended browsers.
Request details:
Request ID: 8636431c686c04ca-HKG
IP: 49.157.13.121
UTC time: 2024-03-12T19:41:31+00:00
Browser: Mozilla/5.0 (Windows NT 10.0; Win64; x64) AppleWebKit/537.36 (KHTML, like Gecko) Chrome/97.0.4692.71 Safari/537.36
About ScienceDirect
Shopping cart
Contact and support
Terms and conditions
Privacy policy
Cookies are used by this site. By continuing you agree to the use of cookies.
Copyright © 2024 Elsevier B.V., its licensors, and contributors. All rights are reserved, including those for text and data mining, AI training, and similar technologies. For all open access content, the Creative Commons licensing terms apply.